Skip to main content

Full text of "Basic Teachings Of The Great Philosophers A Survey Of Their Basic Idea"

See other formats



11342' 





_ ',*% .' ',"'', , '*" ' /' ' f Wfyi^t''^. 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF 
THE GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

A Survey of Their Basic Ideas 



S. E. FROST, JR., PLD. 



REVISED EDITION 



ANCHOR BOOKS 
DOUBLEDAY 

NTF.W VOB1T T.ONTVON TORONTO SYDNEY AUCKLAND 



AN ANCHOR BOOK 
PUBLISHED BY DOUBLEDAY 

a division of Bantam Doubleday Dell Publishing Group, Inc. 
666 Fifth Avenue, New York, New York 10103 

ANCHOR BOOKS, DOUBLEDAY, and the portrayal of an anchor 

are trademarks of Doubleday, a division of Bantam Doubleday 

Dell Publishing Group, Inc. 



Basic Teachings of the Great Philosophers 

was originally published in hardcover by 

Doubleday in 1942. The revised edition was originally 

published in paperback by Dolphin Books in 1962. 

The Anchor Books edition is published by arrangement with Doubleday. 

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data 

Frost, S. E, 1899- 

Basic teachings of the great philosophers: 

a survey of their basic ideas / S, E. Frost. 

Rev. ed., 1st Anchor Books ed, 

p. cm. 
Reprint. Originally published: Garden City, N.Y: 

Doubleday, 1962. 

L Philosophy Introductions. I. Title. 

BD2LF73 1989 8948158 

100-dc20 CIP 

ISBN 0-385-03007-X 

Copyright 1942, 1962, by Doubkday, 
a division of Bantam, Doubkday, Dell Publishing Group, Inc. 

ALL RIGHTS RESERVED 
PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 
FIRST ANCHOR BOOKS EDITION: 
RRC 



CONTENTS 



INTRODUCTION i 

I THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 5 

The Views of the Early Greek Philosophers 6 

Plato's Theory of die Universe 10 

Aristotle's Conception of the Universe 12 
The Views of the Epicureans, Stoics, and 

Skeptics 16 
The Universe According to the Greco-Reli- 
gious Thinkers 18 
The Position of the Early Christian Thinkers 19 
The Positions of the Medieval Christian 

Thinkers 20 
The Views of the Forerunners of the Renais- 
sance 27 
The Universe According to the Philosophers 

of the Renaissance 29 

Descartes 1 Conception of the Universe 31 

Spinoza's Theory of the Universe 33 

The Positions of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume 35 

Leibnitz' Theory of the Universe 39 

Kant's Conception of the Universe 4 

Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel 4 1 

The Views of the Later German Philosophers 44 
The Positions o John Stuart Mill and Herbert 

Spencer 47 



Vlii BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Josiah Royce, William James, and John 

Dewey 49 

The Views of Henri Bergson and George 

Santayana gl 

n MAN'S PLACE IN TBE UNIVERSE 53 

Man's Importance According to the Early 

Greek Philosophers 54 

The Positions of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 56 

The Views of theater Greek Thinkers 58 
Man's Importance According to the Early 

Christian Thinkers 58 
The Views of the Medieval Christian 

Thinkers 59 
As Seen by the Forerunners of the Renais- 
sance 62 
The Positions of Bacon and Hobbes 63 
The Views of Descartes and Spinoza 64 
Man's Place as Seen by Locke, Berkeley, and 

Hume 65 

The Views of Leibnitz 67 

The Position of Rousseau 68 

Kant's View of Man's Importance 68 

Fichte, ScheBing, Schleiennacher, and Hegel 69 

The Views of Later German Thinkers 72 

Man's Place According to Comte 74 

The Positions of Mill and! Spencer 75 

The Views of James, Dewey, and Russell 77 

m WHAT Is GOOD AND WHAT Is EVEL? 80 

Good and Evil According to the Early Greek 

Philosophers 81 
The Ethical Views of Socrates, Plato, and 

Aristotle 83 
Good and Evil According to the Epicureans 

and Stoics 86 

The Position of the Greco-Religious Thinkers 87 
The Ethical Views of the Early Christian 

Thinkers 88 



CONTENTS IX 

The Views of the Medieval Christian 

Thinkers 89 

Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, and Leibnitz 91 

The Ethical Philosophy of Kant 94 

The Views of Fichte and Schopenhauer 95 

According to Mill, Benthani, and Spencer 97 

The Ethical Views of James and Dewey 98 

IV THE NATOBE OF GOD 100 

The Views of the Early Greek Philosophers 102 
Hie Concept of God in the Thought of 

Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 104 

The Position of the Later Greek Thinkers 106 

The Greco-Religious Ideas About God 107 
The Early and Medieval Christian Concep- 

tion of God 108 
Bruno, Boehme, and Otter Forerunners of 

the Renaissance 113 
The Position of Bacon, Hobbes, Descartes, 

and Pascal 13 4 

The Nature of God According to Spinoza 116 
The Views of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and 

Leibnitz "7 

The Concept of God in the Thought of Kant 120 
Fichte, Schelling, Sdbleiermacher, Hegel, and 

Later German Thinkers 1*1 

The Position of Comte, Spencer, and Bradley 1*4 

The Views of James and Dewey 124 



V FATE VERSUS FBEE Wnx 

The Idea of Fate Among the Early Greek 

Thinkers 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 130 

The Views of the Later Greek Philosophers 13^ 

The Position of the Greco-Religious Thinkers 134 
Early and Medieval Christian Thinkers 13S 

The Views of Bacon, Hobbes, Descartes, and 
Spinoza 



X BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

The Position of Locke, of Hume, and of 

Leibnitz 
Fate and Free Will According to Voltaire and 

to Rousseau 145 

Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, and 

Other German Thinkers 146 

The Position of Mill and of Green 150 

The Views of James and Dewey 151 

VI THE SOOT, AND IMMORTAXJTY 153 

The Soul as Viewed by the Early Greek 

Philosophers 155 
The Soul and Immortality According to Plato 

and Aristotle 157 
The Position of the Later Greek Thinkers 159 
The Views of Plotinus 160 
The Early and Medieval Christian Concep- 
tion of the Soul 160 
The Soul According to the Forerunners of the 

Renaissance 162 
The Views of Bacon and Hobbes 163 
The Views of Descartes and Spinoza 163 
Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Leibnitz 165 
The Soul and Immortality According to Kant 167 
Fichte, Schleiennacher, Herbart, and Scho- 
penhauer 168 
Recent and Present-Day Conceptions of the 

Soul and Immortality 170 

VII MAN AND THE STATE 173 

The State as Viewed by tibe Early Greek 

Philosophers 178 

The State According to Socrates, Plato, and 

Aristotle 181 

The Positions of the Later Greek Thinkers 184 

The Views of the Early Christian Thinkers 186 

The Views of the Medieval Christian Think- 
ers 188 
The State as Viewed by the Forerunners of 

the Renaissance 192 



CONTENTS 3d 

Machiavellf s Conception of the State 193 
Grotius, Hobbes, and Other Thinkers of the 

Renaissance 194 
The Views of Spinoza, Locke, and Adam 

Smith 196 

The Position of Voltaire and of Rousseau 198 
The State According to Hegel, Marx, and 

Lassalle 199 

De Maistre, Saint-Simon, and Comte 200 

The Views of Mill and Spencer 202 

Nietzsche's Conception of the State 204 

The Views of Dewey and Recent Thinkers 205 

VIII MAN AND EDUCATION 207 
Education as Viewed by the Early Greek 

Philosophers 209 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 210 

The Roman Conception of Education 212 

Early Christian Conception of Education 213 

St. Benedict and the Monastic Way of Life 214 
Education in the Middle Ages and Early 

Renaissance 215 
Martin Luther and the Protestant Refor- 
mation 217 
The Views of Bacon and Hobbes 218 
, Comenius* Philosophy of Education 218 
Locke and Rousseau 219 
Pestalozzfs Conception of Education 
Herbart's View of Education 
Froebel's Conception of Education 



IX MEND AND MATTER 

Mind and Matter as Contrasted by the Early 

Greek Thinkers 228 
Plato, Aristotle, and the Later Greek Phi- 
losophers 230 
The Positions of Philo and St. Augustine 333 
According to the Medieval Christian Thinkers 234 
Roger Bacon and Paracelsus 235 



Xii BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Francis Bacon and Hobbes 236 

Descartes and Spinoza 238 

Locke, Berkeley, and Hume 240 

The Views of Leibnitz 241 

Kant and Later German Philosophers 241 

Bradley, Royce, and Bergson 244 

Comte, James, Dewey, Santayana 244 

X IDEAS AJSTD THINKING 246 

What Thinking Meant to the Early Greek 

Philosophers 247 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 249 

The Views of the Later Greek Philosophers 250 

The Medieval Christian View 251 
Galileo and the Beginning of the Scientific 

Attitude 253 

Bacon, Descartes, Spinoza 254 

Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Leibnitz 256 

Kant, Fichte, Hegel 257 

Comte, Mill, Spencer 260 

James and Dewey 260 

XI SOME RECENT APPROACHES TO PHILOSOPHY 263 
Kierkegaard and the Beginnings of Existen- 
tialism 264 
The Views of Heidegger, Jaspers, and Sartre 265 
Three Philosophers of Science: Whitehead, 

RusseD, and Moore 266 

Logical Positivism 268 

Two Philosophers of the Spirit 269 

Some Current Philosophers in the Religious 

Tradition 270 

CONCLUSION 272 

BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 275 

INDEX 297 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF 
THE GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 



INTRODUCTION 



Everyone, whether he be plowman or banker, clerk or 
captain, citizen or ruler, is, in a real sense, a philosopher. 
Being human, having a highly developed brain and nervous 
system, he must think; and thinking is the pathway to 
philosophy. 

The world in which we live will not let us rest. It keeps 
prodding us, challenging us with problems to be solved, 
demanding that we act wisely or be destroyed by the 
forces which inhabit our world* In this way experiences are 
born hungers and satisfactions, pains and pleasures, sights, 
feelings, sounds, and a host of others. 

But we cannot rest contented with a mass of unrelated 
experiences scattered at random throughout life. We must 
take our experiences and weave them into some kind of a 
pattern, a whole which is more or less satisfying. This pat- 
tern, this whole, is our philosophy* 

Your philosophy, then, is the meaning which the world 
has for you. It is your answer to the question, "Why?" 
Having fitted your experiences into a whole, having re- 
lated them to each other, you say of the world, This is 
the way things fit together. This is the world as I under- 
stand it. This is my philosophy." 

Your philosophy and the philosophy of those whose 
names appear in books of Philosophy diflEer only in that 
the latter use more experiences in weaving their patterns, 
those patterns which satisfy them, and are more careful 
and thorough in fitting their experiences into a pattern. 
Theirs is a more complete, more all-inclusive pattern, more 
logical, more consistent, more accurate. 



2 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

What are the great philosophic problems which puzzle 
all of us, and which the great philosophers throughout 
the ages have sought to answer? We find that there are 
ten major problems which have always challenged thinking 
men and women. 

The first of these problems is: What is the nature of the 
universe? Did this universe come into being through an 
act of divine creation or is it the result of a gradual process 
of growth? Of what substance or substances is the uni- 
verse created? How does the universe change? 

The second problem is: What is mans place in the uni- 
verse? Is the human individual the crowning achievement 
of a growing and creating universe, or is he a mere speck 
of dust in unlimited space? Does the universe care for you 
and me, or are we of no more concern than a grain of 
sand on a vast beach? Can we mould the universe to our 
liking, or will it eventually destroy us? 

The third great problem is: What is good and what is 
evil? How are we to know the good from the evil? Has 
some divine power set standards of good and evil for all 
times, or are good and evil matters of the local culture? 
Is good in the very nature of things, or is it something 
which we can decide for ourselves? How can we distin- 
guish good from evil? 

A fourth problem is: What is the nature of God? Is God 
a being very much like man who governs the universe, or 
is He a spirit which pervades everything? Is God all-power- 
ful, all-good, and all-just, or is He just another individual 
who has little more power or insight than you and I? 

A fifth problem is related to the question of Fat e versus 
free will? Are we free individuals who can make our 
choices and determine our actions without let or hindrance, 
or are we determined by a fate over which we have no 
control? Can we determine tomorrow in any significant 
sense, or is it all determined for us from the beginning of 
time? 

The sixth problem is concerned with the Soul and im~ 
mortality. What is the soul about which we have heard so 
much? Is it of such a nature that it lives after the death of 



INTRODUCTION 3 

the body, or does it die with the body? Is there a future 
life in which good is rewarded and evil punished, or does 
death mark the end of everything? 

A seventh problem consists of man's questions about 
Man and the state* Is the state a human creation which 
has been brought into being to serve man, or is it some- 
thing that has divine origin? Are the rulers of states given 
their power by those they rule or by God? Does man have 
a right to rebel against his rulers and create a new kind of 
state? What is the best form of state and what is the worst? 

The eighth problem is that of Man and education. 
What is education? Why do we have a system of educa- 
tion and why do we send our children to school? Who 
shall control education, the people or the state? Is educa- 
tion designed to make free men or to make men who will 
serve blindly an all-powerful state? 

The ninth problem has to do with Mind and matter. 
Which is superior, mind or matter? Is matter a creation of 
mind, or is mind merely another kind of matter? Can mind 
be superior and free from matter, or is it so tied up with 
matter that it is doomed? Is matter the source of all evil in 
the universe? How can mind remain pure and at the same 
time inhabit a body? 

And the tenth problem is concerned with Ideas and 
thinking. Where do we get our ideas? Are they inherent 
in the very nature of our minds, or do they come to us 
from outside the mind? What are the laws of thinking? 
How can we be sure that our thinking is correct? Is think- 
ing significant in the universe or is it a mere sham? 

This book brings together the answers which the great 
philosophers of all times have offered to the problems 
which you and I think about today. They have toiled to 
form an answer that seems to them satisfactory. We have 
brought it to you. 

Our method is to bring together what each pMlosopher 
has written on each of these problems as briefly and con- 
cisely as possible. This is done so that you, busy as you 
are, do not have to read long discourses on philosophy to 
discover that which will help you in your thinking. By 



4 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

reading any one of the chapters in this book, you can get a 
dear picture of what the philosophers down through the 
ages have said about one of your real problems. 

Although each chapter is a unit to itself and can be read 
without reference to the other chapters, it is advisable for 
the reader to begin with the first chapter and go through 
the book This will give you a wide view of the great phi- 
losophers and will help you to see each problem or group 
of problems in relation to the other problems and groups 
of problems in the book. 

Following these ten chapters arranged according to phil- 
osophical problems, we include a new chapter dealing 
with Some Recent Approaches to Philosophy. The views 
of the men discussed in this eleventh chapter apply to 
many of the problems which are the topics of earlier chap- 
ters and should be considered in relation to them. But 
most readers will prefer to have these newer approaches 
grouped together at this one point in the book, as a survey 
of important aspects of recent philosophical thought. 

At the end of the book you will find Biographical Notes 
concerning the philosophers whom you meet in the pages 
of the book. This section should be used as a quick refer- 
ence when you want to know the exact dates during which 
the philosopher lived or other pertinent facts about 



Chapter I 
THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 

THALES PYTHAGORAS HEBACLITUS 

PABMENIDES PLATO ABISTOTLE 

AUGUSTINE AQUINAS BACON HOBBES 

DESCARTES SPINOZA LOCKE KANT HEGEL 

MILL DEWEY BERGSON SANTAYANA 



The world in which you and 1 tive was here long be- 
fore as. How did it come to be? Was it created, or 
has it existed forever? Who or what made it, and how 
was it made? Are the trees, stars, men and women 
really "there* or are they mere creations of our minds 
or of the mind of God? How came this universe to be, 
and what is it made of? 



There is no one of us who has not wondered how the 
universe came into being. This world, with its flowers, 
rivers, rocks, sky, stars, sun, and moon, all did not come 
about by mere chance, we reason. All that we see around 
us, and all that we know of, must have become what it is 
today by some process. If we fcould understand this proc- 
ess, we would understand the nature of the universe. 

The earliest people that we have any records of had 
theories of the beginning and nature of things. They wove 
these ideas into their religion and the priests and religious 
men explained them to the young men, who in turn passed 
them on to their children. In the first book of the Bible, 
Genesis, is one of these theories. Here we are told that God 



6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHJLOSCXPHEBS 

created the world out of nothing in six days. He made light 
and darkness, the sun, moon, and stats, the earth and the 
waters, and finally made all living things, including man. 
Then, when all was completed and man along with woman 
was placed in a beautiful garden, God came to die world 
and walked in the garden, contented with his handiwork. 

The Views of the Early Greek Philosophers 
The earliest philosophers, the Greeks, were greatly in- 
terested in this problem of the nature of the universe. In- 
deed, it was the first problem they attacked. Just as chil- 
dren break open their toys to discover how they are made, 
so these philosophers of the childhood of the human race 
sought to break apart the universe in their minds, and to 
penetrate the mystery of the making of all things found 
in it "What is the 'stuff from which aH things come?" they 
asked themselves. "How does it happen that there are 
many things in the universe?" 

THALES, who lived in Miletus in Ancient Greece (about 
600 B.C.), was the first to propose a solution of this prob- 
lem. He told his neighbors that water was the original 
stuff." He saw water turning into a solid, ice, when it was 
frozen, and into air, steam, when heated. Therefore, he 
reasoned that everything, from the hardest rock to the 
lightest air, originally came from water and in the end re- 
turned to water. 

A little kter another citizen of Miletus, ANAXIMAHDEB, 
wrote that the original "stuff" of which everything in the 
universe was made was not, as Thales had suggested, 
water, but was a living mass which filled aH space. He 
called this mass "the infinite.- In the beginning, he told his 
fellows, this mass, this "infinite," was whole, not broken 
into pieces. But it contained "motion." This "motion- 
caused it to begin to move up and down, back and forth, 
and around. Slowly pieces were broken off from the mass 
so that eventually afl the things which we now have in the 
universe came into being. As the motion continued, he be- 
lieved, these innumerable pieces would be brought back to- 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 7 

gether and the mass, the "infinite,'* would assume its origi- 
nal unbroken unity. 

Anaximander wrote a very detailed account of how he 
believed the world, the sun, the stars, air, animals, fishes, 
and man developed out of this original mass. 

A third resident of Miletus, ANAXIMINES, was not satis- 
fied with the accounts which had been given by these two 
thinkers who had preceded him. He suggested that the 
original "stuff* of which all else in the universe was made 
was air. He realized that men and animals breathe air and 
are able to live, and reasoned that the air turned into flesh, 
bone, and blood. Therefore, he went on to reason that air 
could become wind, clouds, water, earth, and stone. 

These three philosophers of Miletus were interested in 
discovering the original "stuff" of which all else in the uni- 
verse was made. They were followed by a group of phi- 
losophers who, although they were interested in the same 
problem, were more interested in finding out in what ways 
the many things in the universe were related. These were 
the Pythagoreans, a group or school founded by Pythag- 
oras. 

PYTHAGORAS and the Pythagoreans were impressed by 
the fact that many things in the universe were related in 
ways that could be stated by numbers. For example, the 
tone of a wire or piece of gut is related to its length in a 
manner that can be expressed in numbers.. So, they rea- 
soned, number must be this "stuff* for which philosophers 
were looking. To them numbers became things, entities, 
and they taught that the whole universe was built of num- 
bers. They believed that since the harmonious octave 
reached over eight notes, eight was friendship. A point, 
they held, was one, and a line two. And on they went to 
develop a most complicated system of numbers in their ef- 
fort to show how everything was actually made of num- 
bers. 

All the philosophers whom we have mentioned so far 
took it for granted that things change. They saw change 
all about them and did not recognize it as a problem. 
Water changed into ice or into steam, air became wind, 



8 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT MOLOSOPHEBS 

numbers became things* motion was in everything produc- 
ing these changes. For them this fact just was; and why be 
concerned about it? 

But as philosophers continued to work with this problem 
of the nature of the universe, they began to recognize that 
change was itself a problem. Wliat is it? How does it come 
about? Is there really change, or do we just imagine that 
things change? These questions began to rear their heads 
end demand an answer. 

This fact of change so impressed HERACIJTUS, a son of a 
noble family of Ephesus, that lie concluded that fire was 
the original "stuff* of which all else in the universe was 
made. Fire, he believed, was forever changing, never still, 
never tie same. Since everything is constantly changing, 
since change is the fundamental characteristic of the uni- 
verse, the forever-changing fire must be the material of the 
universe. "You could not," he wrote, "step twice into the 
same river, for other and yet other waters are ever flowing 
on." There is nothing permanent, stable. Change is all 
that is. 

We may think that we see things that do not change, 
Heraditus taught, but we are fooled. If we could really see 
what is happening, if we had eyes powerful enough to see 
exactly what is happening, we would realize that even the 
most stable thing in the universe is actually changing all 
the time. The universe, then, is ruled by "strife.'* The mo- 
ment a thing is made, strife begins to break it up. All 
things are changing all the time, and there is nothing per- 
manent 

While Heraditus was preaching the doctrine that 
change is tike essence of aH things, there were Greek phi- 
losophers living in Elea who taught that change is impos- 
sible. Nothing, they said, can possibly change. If we think 
we see change, we are fooled; for it cannot be. XENOPH- 
ANES, the earliest of these Eleatics, believed that the 
universe was a solid mass which was forever unchangeable, 
immovable. The parts might diange, but the whole could 
never change. PABMENIDES, another member of this school 
at Elea, taught that all change is inconceivable. If there 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE Q 

were such a thing as change, he reasoned, something would 
have to come from nothing, and that was impossible. 
What we see with our eyes is not true but an illusion. The 
universe is unchangeable and immovable, ZENO, a third 
member of this school, sought to prove that anyone who 
attempted to prove the existence of change would contra- 
dict himself. 

These arguments of Heraclitus and of the Eleatics were 
so interesting to philosophers that some set about to see if 
the positions of both sides could be reconciled in some way. 
They felt that this "riddle of permanence and change" had 
to be solved, and they turned their attention to the task 

EMPEDOCLES agreed with the Eleatics when he said that 
in the strict sense there can be no change, but he also 
agreed with Heraclitus in holding that there is "mingling 
and separation.* The universe, said he, is composed of four 
dements or "roots of things": earth, air, fire, and water. 
There are millions and millions of very tiny particles of 
each element These combine in various ways to form the 
many things in the universe. As filings decay or change, the 
elements separate. Then they may come together or mingle 
again in another thing. The elements never change. They 
are permanent Thus, actually there is no change, but 
merely a mingling and separating of elements. This min- 
gling and separating is caused, he believed, by Love and 
Hate. Love brings the elements together to form things. 
Hate breaks them apart 

Empedocles* solution of the problem of change and per- 
manence interested ANAXAGOBAS but did not satisfy him. 
After much study, he reached the conclusion that there 
must be more than four elements. Indeed, he became con- 
vinced that there were untold millions of elements or sub- 
stances. Each of these was in untold millions of tiny pieces. 
Flesh was a result of millions of flesh elements coming 
together in one place. Bone was the result of millions of 
bone elements combining. So with everything in the uni- 
verse. Numbers of elements come together and the thing is 
formed. No element can be changed into another. There- 
fore there is in reality no change. But as these elements 



1O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

combine, separate, and recombine, we have change. These 
elements combine and separate, not because of anything 
in them, but because of the rotation of the heavenly bodies. 
As a whirling motion was first produced in the original 
mass of elements lying quiet, they began to combine and 
the many things in the universe were formed 

All of this thinking paved the way for another important 
group of early Greek thinkers, the Atontfsts. The most 
noted members of this group were LEUGPPUS and DEMOG- 
BTTUS. These men agreed with their predecessors that 
change was a result of the mingling and separating of tiny 
units. But they disagreed with them as to the nature of 
these elements. All the thinkers before the Atomists had! 
taught that the elements differed in quality. There were 
flesh elements, bone elements, hair element?, and so on. 
The flesh elements were different from the bone or hair 
elements. The Atomists taught that all units, or atoms, are 
alike as far as quality is concerned. Some have hooks, 
others eyes, and still others grooves, humps, or depressions. 
As these atoms unite in different ways and in different 
numbers, things are formed. Each atom has motion inside 
it, so that it moves about of its own accord and attaches 
itself to other atoms. 

Change, then, for the Atomists was a matter of the min- 
gling and separating of atoms. The atoms never changed, 
but were eternal, minutely small, and all alike. Real change 
of an atom was impossible. The only change possible was 
as atoms grouped themselves together to form a thing or 
separated from each other. 

Thus the early Greeks, working with the problem of the 
nature of the universe for about 250 years, reached the 
conclusion that everything in the universe was composed 
by the uniting in various ways and in various numbers of 
tiny atoms which were all alike. 

Plato's Theory of the Universe 

None of these early theories satisfied PLATO, one of the 
greatest thinkers of all times. For Plato, the world which 
we see, touch, and experience through our other senses is 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 11 

not real, but is a copy world In it we find things changing, 
coming and going, and in great abundance. It is a world of 
many mistakes, deformities, evils. It exists and we experi- 
ence it every day. But it is not real. 

There is, however, a real world in which are to be found 
the true things of which aD. that we experience are mere 
copies. He called this the world of "ideas." Here is to be 
found the ideal tree of which all trees which we see are 
copies, the ideal house, and ideas of all other objects in the 
universe. These are perfect, do not change in any way, 
never fade or die, but remain forever. 

These "ideas* or "forms" (Plato uses both words to de- 
scribe them) were never created, but have existed from 
the very beginning in just the perfect state in which they 
will always exist They are independent of all things, and 
are not influenced by the changes which take place in the 
world which we experience through our senses. These ob- 
jects which we experience are reflections of these "eternal 
patterns." 

All "ideas'* are arranged in the "ideal world" in order; 
the "highest idea," the idea of perfect goodness, being at 
the top. 

But there is another principle in the universe, that of 
"matter." This is all that "ideas" are not It may be thought 
of as the raw material upon which the "ideas" are im- 
pressed. Let us think, for example, of the work of a sculp- 
tor. He has an idea of a figure which he wishes to repro- 
duce in marble, let us say. Now, this idea is independent 
of all the marble in the universe. But the marble is neces- 
sary for its realization so that others may experience it 
through their senses. Therefore, the sculptor takes a slab 
of marble and creates a statue. The marble, as raw ma- 
terial, has the idea impressed upon it The sculptor may 
make many statues without affecting his idea in the least 

In this way Plato thought that title world was created. 
Nature, all that we experience through our senses, owes 
its existence to the influence of the world of ideas upon 
matter. It is not the "real" world, but an impression of the 
"real" world upon matter. Thus, all the mistakes, all the 



Ifc BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

changes, all the imperfections of the world of our senses are 
due to matter and not to the ideas. 

La one of Plato's famous Dialogues, the Tvmaeus, he tells 
us how the world o our senses was created. There was an 
"architect," the "Demiurge/* who brought the ideal world 
and matter together just as a sculptor might bring his idea 
and marble together to produce a statue. This "Demiurge" 
had perfect ideas of everything, and he had a great mass of 
matter. Plato never tells us where either the "Demiurge," 
ideas, or matter came from originally. They were just there 
when things began. As the "Demiurge"* brought an idea in 
touch with some matter, a thing was created. Indeed, a 
great many things were created from one idea. There is 
one perfect idea of an oak tree, but there are millions of 
oak trees. So with everything else in the universe, it is a 
combination of a perfect idea and matter. And the idea is 
not at aQ influenced by this. It remains perfect and un- 
changed forever. 

Plato has been called an Idealist because he thought 
that the real world was this world of ideas. Some students 
of his philosophy say that it would be truer to call him an 
"Idea-ist** since he was interested in ideas. But, whatever 
we choose to call him, Idealist or Idea-ist, we recognize 
that he believed the universe to consist of a realm of per- 
fect and unchanging ideas and matter. The world of ideas 
was, for him, the true, the real, world. That which we ex- 
perience through our senses was, for him, a copy world, an 
"unreal world** in this sense. It was a world of objects pro- 
duced by impressing a perfect idea upon matter. All of its 
imperfections came from the fact that it was impossible to 
impress the idea perfectly upon matter; matter is imper- 
fect and thus distorts the idea to some extent, twists it out 
of shape. 

Aristotle's Conception of the Universe 

Democritus and the Atomists, as we have seen, ex- 
plained the universe in terms of moving identical atoms. 
Plato explained it in terms of perfect ideas which somehow 
were impressed upon matter. ARISTOTLE, who stands with 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 13 

Plato among the world's very greatest philosophers, at- 
tempted to arrive at a theory of th# universe which would 
mediate between that of the Atomists and of Plato. 

Aristotle was willing to admit that matter does exist. And 
as a pupil of Plato, he believed that ideas existed. But, he 
wanted to bring these together in a way that would be 
more satisfying than the solution suggested by Plato. His 
problem was, then How can perfect, changeless, eternal 
ideas be impressed upon lifeless matter? And his answer 
was that ideas, or "forms* as he called them, are not out- 
side of and above things, are not "transcendent," but are in 
things. He taught that form and matter are always and 
eternally together. Therefore, the world which we experi- 
ence through our senses is not, as Plato taught, a mere copy 
of the real world, but is the real world. Here form and 
matter are one, and neither can be experienced separately. 
Only by thinking can we separate the two; actually we al- 
ways find them together. 

Let us take an acorn as an example. An acorn is a unity 
of form and matter. We recognize the form "acorn," which 
is characteristic of all acorns. Wherever we see an acorn, 
we discover this form. But our example is a particular 
acorn. Never do Ve have the form "acorn" divorced from a 
particular acorn. But, in addition to form, our example has 
matter. The form "acorn** seeks to realize itself in matter, 
and the result is the acorn which we have. The more per- 
fect the acorn, the more perfectly the form is realized. 

But the acorn may become an oak tree. Thus this acorn 
which we hold in our hands is matter, and the form which 
it seeks to realize is the oak tree. As the acorn is planted 
and as it grows, it is striving to realize the form of the oak 
tree; it is seeking to become an oak tree. In the same way, 
the oak tree may become oak boards which are used to 
build tables, chairs, or other pieces of furniture. Here the 
oak tree is matter, and the particular piece of furniture is 
the form which the oak tree seeks to realize. 

In every case, the acorn, the oak tree, the piece of fur- 
niture, we have matter and form. At every stage the ob- 
ject which exists is both the realization of a form and also 



14 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

matter for the realization of another form. Thus, forms 
never change, but are eternally the same. The form "acorn" 
is always the same and never becomes the form "oak tree." 
But matter takes on different forms as it changes. First it 
took on the form of an acorn, then the form of an oak tree, 
and then the form of a piece of furniture. And the process 
goes on indefinitely as change takes place. Matter is always 
taking on, striving to realize, forms. 

Wherever we look in nature, in the universe, Aristotle 
taught, we find both matter and form. For him there can 
be no matter divorced from form, nor can there be any 
form divorced from matter. And both matter and form are 
eternal, never being created or destroyed. Thus the entire 
universe can be explained, he believed, as the process in 
which matter constantly seeks to realize different forms, to 
become what it can become. 

If we wish to understand the universe, then, we may 
think of it in terms of a sculptor producing a statue. But, 
while in the case of Plato the sculptor is independent, free 
from his marble* in the case of Aristotle he is dependent 
on his marble. His idea of a perfect statue is actually in the 
marble, a form which the marble seeks to realize. 

Therefore, Aristotle taught that every object in the uni- 
verse had four causes. The first corresponds to the idea of 
the statue which the artist has before he begins work, the 
form which is to be realized. This he called the "formal 
cause." Then there is the marble with which the artist is to 
work, the matter. This is the "material cause." The third 
cause is that by which the statue is made, the tools em- 
ployed to make the statue. This he called the "efficient 
cause" or "moving cause." The fourth cause is the purpose 
or end for which the statue is made, that for the sake of 
which the work is done. This he termed the "final cause." 

For Aristotle, all these causes are operating in the thing 
as it develops, changes, grows, becomes. We must not 
think of an artist separated from his marble, but rather of 
an artist as a part of his marble. A better illustration may 
be that of a man seeking to become, let us say, a doctor. 



THE NATUBE OP THE UNIVERSE 1$ 

He seeks to change himself into something else. His idea 
of "doctor" is the "formal cause"; his body with all its 
characteristics is the "material cause**; that which he does 
to change himself is the "efficient cause"; and the reason he 
makes this change from what he is originally to a doctor 
is the "final cause." Here the man is within that which is 
changed and he is what is created. 

For Aristotle all motion is to be explained as the union 
of form and matter. When matter offers resistance to form 
we have deformities, mistakes, evils. However, matter is 
also a help to form in that it seeks to realize form, to be- 
come something. 

It is clear from what we have already said that Aris- 
totle's world is not a purely mechanical something. It is 
not a mere mass of units or atoms moving about and form- 
ing objects, as the Atomists taught Rather, it is charac- 
terized by purposes which matter seeks to realize. There is 
striving in this universe, a seeking to become. We call such 
a world "teleological," not a world of mere chance but one 
of purpose. 

If the acorn seeks to become an oak tree and the oak tree 
seeks to become a piece of furniture, where does the proc- 
ess stop? Is everything seeking to become something else, 
and is there no end to the chain? Aristotle believed that 
there was an end. This he thought of as the first cause or 
the "unmoved mover." It is pure form without any matter. 
It does not cause anything else, but just is. It is not in mat- 
ter and does not seek to impress itself upon matter. We 
cannot experience it, but we can think it. 

Thus, at one extreme we may think of pure matter with- 
out any form, formless matter, And at the other extreme 
we may think of pure form, matterless form. But we can- 
not experience either. The universe which we experience, 
the world of chairs, stars, earth, men, and all other things, 
is a world in which matter and form are united. And each 
object is the realization of a form and is the matter for the 
realization of still another form. In this way Aristotle at- 
tempted to solve the problem of the universe. 



l6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF tSEREAT PHXLOSOPHEBS 

The Views of the Epicureans, Stoics, and Skeptics 

With the coming of EPICUITOS and the Epicureans, many 
thinkers devoted their attention largely to the problem of 
how to live a good life. However, even these philosophers 
recognized that one could not be good unless he understood 
the world in which he had to live this life. Hius they strug- 
gled with the problem of the nature of the universe. 

Epicurus based his solution largely on the theory of De- 
mocritus and the Atomists which we have already studied. 
He taught that the real things in the universe are bodies 
which we experience through the senses. These bodies are 
made up of small units or atoms which differ in size, 
weight, and shape. As they come together in various 
ways, the bodies which we see are formed. Then, as they 
separate, these bodies disappear and we experience them 
no longer. 

The universe, Epicurus taught, came to be by mere 
chance. Atoms have the power to swerve from a straight 
line. Thus, in the beginning, all atoms were falling straight 
down in space. Being able to swerve, some went one way 
and some another, deviating from the straight line. In this 
way aH the bodies of the universe have been formed and 
are being formed. 

The atoms cannot be destroyed or divided into smaller 
units. They have existed just as they now are from the be- 
ginning and will continue to exist in the same way forever. 

The Stoics, a school of Greek thinkers founded by ZENO 
during the fourth century before Christ, were as interested 
as were the Epicureans in the problem of the good life, or 
"ethics" as it is called. But they too developed an explana- 
tion of the nature of the universe which is important. 

These philosophers agreed with Aristotle that the uni- 
verse is composed of two principles: form or "force" and 
matter. Force moves and acts, while matter is acted upon. 
These two principles are not separated from each other, as 
Plato taught, but are united in every object. Further, both 
force and matter are, for the Stoics, bodies. The bodies 
which are force are very fine-grained, while those which 



THE NATUBE OF THE UNIVERSE VJ 

are matter are coarse and formless. Thus, everything in the 
universe is a body, is corporeal. 

All the forces in the universe form a force which is in 
everything, a sort of fire which is the active soul of the uni- 
verse. The Stoics thought of this world soul as fire because 
they believed that heat produced everything and moved 
everything. Heat, for them, is the giver of life. Conse- 
quently, fire is the basic principle of the universe. 

This fire, or world soul, is related to everything in the 
universe just as the soul of a man is related to his body. 
Indeed, the world is merely the body of the world soul 
From the original fire, the Stoics taught, air, water, 
earth, and all else in the universe arise. These four ele- 
ments, fire, air, water, and earth (which were also the 
four elements of Empedocles), combine in many ways to 
form the things of the universe. And through every object 
in the universe the divine principle flows, making it alive. 
The Stoics were not willing, as were the Epicureans, to 
think of the universe as something that just happened by 
chance. Nor were they willing to go along with the Epi- 
cureans to the extent of holding that the universe is purely 
mechanical. Their principle of force was alive, and the uni- 
verse which came into being was also alive. For them the 
universe was a perfect sphere or ball floating in empty 
space, a ball held together and made alive by its soul 
From the time of Thales to that of the Stoics, thinkers 
had been busy attempting to account for the universe, to 
explain how it w^s made, to develop a theory of the nature 
of things. Each one wove a different theory and offered 
evidence to prove that he was right. 

This diversity of theories and explanations struck a group 
of Greek thinkers as proof of the fact that man is unable to 
know what the universe is or how it came into being. This 
group is known as the Skeptics, and its founder was 
PYRRHO. Its members felt that all attempts to explain the 
nature of the universe were futile, a waste of time, for, they 
argued, man cannot know the nature of things. All we see 
is the world around us. Our senses give conflicting evidence. 
Different men have different reports to make. We have no 



l8 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

way of telling whose report is correct, whose is true to the 
real nature of the world. Therefore, the Skeptics were will- 
ing to give up the search, to say, "We do not know, and 
no man can know." They recommended that men be 
practical, accept what they experience through the senses, 
follow custom. Their answer to the problem of the nature 
of the universe was one of despair, and they abandoned 
all further attempts to work with the problem. 

The Universe According to the Greco-Religious Thinkers 
At about this time, toward the close of the pre-Christian 
era, men were tinning to religions and seeking comfort in 
them. They were confused, tired mentally, and lost among 
the many conflicting theories which had been developed 
in the past. The time was ripe, then, for merging the many 
religious doctrines and beliefs with one or more of the 
Greek philosophies which had come down to that day in a 
more or less garbled form. 

PHH.O, a Jew living in Alexandria in Egypt, was the 
leader of the attempt to merge Judaism, the religion of the 
ancient Jews, with Greek philosophies. For him there was 
God who was so pure and far above everything in this 
world that he could not possibly come into contact with it. 
Thus, to account for the universe, Philo taught that there 
were many powers, or spirits, which radiated from God 
as light might radiate from a lamp. One of these powers, 
which he called the "Logos," was the creator of the world. 
This Logos, he taught, worked with matter and out of it 
created everything in the universe. In this way, God, 
through the Logos, created the universe. Further, every- 
thing in the universe is a copy of an idea in the mind of 
God. This reminds us of Plato's belief that the world which 
we experience through our senses is a copy of ideas in the 
ideal world. And, indeed, Philo was attempting here to 
reconcile Plato's philosophy with the Jewish religion. 

Other religious-minded thinkers attempted to do the 
same thing, reconciling their religious beliefs with Greek 
philosophy. One of the most noted was PLOTINUS, who was 
born in Egypt in the third century of the Christian era and 



THE NATUBE OF THE UNIVERSE 1Q 

taught in Rome. His theory was very much like that of 
Philo. Out of a pure God flow beings, or emanations, as a 
stream might flow from an inexhaustible source, or as light 
flows from the sun without affecting the sun. The further 
the light is from its source, the dimmer it becomes. At the 
far extreme is darkness or matter. 

Between God and matter Plotinus taught that there ex- 
isted mind, soul. The soul acts upon matter and the uni- 
verse is created. Matter, then, is the substance and soul is 
the form of all things. 

In the thinking of all these men we see clearly the 
theories of Plato, Aristotle, and others. The world is, in 
each case, a combination of an idea or form and matter. As 
the two come together in different ways, different objects 
are created. 

The Position of the Early Christian Thinkers 
This attempt to account for the universe, which is a 
theater of change and imperfection, and at the same time 
teach that God is perfect and unchanging was continued 
by the Christians. Those men who sought to reconcile 
Christianity with Greek philosophy were known as Apolo- 
gists. They taught that the universe contains traces of 
something different from pure matter and thus points to a 
God who is eternal, unchanging, and good. This God is the 
First Cause of everything in the universe, the creator of 
the universe. For them the "ideas" of Plato and the forms 
of Aristotle become God. God is the eternal and abiding 
principle in all change, the eternal pattern which never 
changes. He is the unity of all forms, all ideas. Through 
divine emanations he has created the world; and everything 
in the world, in so far as it is a part of God, strives to be 
more like God, to return to Him. The Creator fashioned 
the world from matter which He created out of nothing. 
The pattern of the world is in His mind. 

One of the greatest thinkers among these early Christian 
philosophers, one who worked out the theory of the Apolo- 
gists most completely, was AUGUSTINE, who became Saint 
Augustine. God, he taught, created matter out of nothing 



20 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

and then created everything in the universe. The forms 
which he impressed upon matter were in God's mind from 
the beginning of time, and even before, for God existed 
before there was any time. Indeed, God created time and 
space also. Thus everything that is or ever shall be is a 
creation of God and must follow His laws and will. Here 
again we see the influence of the Greeks in the belief that 
the universe is the result of the coming together of matter 
and form. 

But the Christian thinkers went further than the Greeks 
in that they attempted to account for the existence of mat- 
ter. You will remember that the Greeks simply accepted 
matter as well as the ideas or forms as existing from the 
beginning. The Christians put the ideas or forms in God's 
mind and went on to say that God created matter out of 
nothing. After He had created matter, He had something 
upon which to impress ideas or forms. 

Further, these Christian philosophers taught that the 
ideas or forms, being in the mind of God, were divine. 
Theref ore, in so far as things axe ideas or forms impressed 
on matter, they seek God, try to return to Him. But matter 
holds them back. Matter, which God has created, is the 
principle which makes it necessary for things to struggle in 
their attempt to become divine. 

Augustine lived during the fourth century of the Chris- 
tian era. He saw the great Roman Empire, which had been 
established by the Caesars, falling to pieces, and watched 
the barbarians from the north gradually moving down into 
the empire and even toward Rome. He lived near the be- 
ginning of that period in history known as the Dark Ages, 
a period when these ignorant, crude barbarians swarmed 
over the Roman Empire and destroyed the civilization 
which had been building since the early days of the Greeks. 

The Positions of the Medieval Christian Thinkers 

After Augustine for centuries few men had! time for 
thinking about the universe and its nature. Philosophy was 
gradually neglected, and those who did endeavor to think 
merely repeated the philosophies of those who had gone 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 21 

before them, Plato, Aristotle, the Epicureans, the Stoics, 
and others. Most of the books written during this period 
were "remarkable only for their nieagerness of original 
thought.** Indeed, by the time of the seventh century the 
cloud of ignorance had so settled over Western Europe 
that this century and the next, the eighth, have been re- 
ferred to as "perhaps the darkest period of our Western 
European civilization.'' 

By the middle of the ninth century some men were be- 
ginning to think again. By this time the Christian church 
was in complete control of Western Europe. It dominated 
everything, the state, men's lives, and all education and 
thought Those who did attempt to think had to confine 
their thinking to the beliefs which the church accepted. 
Thus, all thinking was limited to church doctrines. In most 
cases men merely attempted to show that the beliefs of the 
church were true, reasonable. 

So, when JOHN Scorus EBIGENA wrote during the ninth 
century, he tried to show that the orthodox theory of the 
creation of everything in the universe was reasonable. He 
taught that God created the world out of nothing or "out 
of himself, the causeless first cause.** Before God created 
the world, he had a complete pattern of the world in his 
mind. Then, as a light is radiated from its source so the 
world was radiated from God. Consequently, the universe 
and God are one, but God is more than the universe. God 
is in his creation and his creation is in him, 

Since God is one and is not divided, Erigena taught, so 
the universe is $ unity. We may see differences, many indi- 
vidual objects, but they are all one. They are all God. We 
call this belief "pantheism.** This universe is "an expression 
of the thought of God" and therefore cannot exist apart 
from him. Being God, everything in the universe strives to 
return to the unity of God. 

From Plato to Erigena philosophers had been, as we 
have seen, explaining the universe as the union of ideas or 
forms and matter. In every instance the idea or form is 
thought of as a real thing existing before it was impressed 
upon matter. Plato thought of ideas as existing before 



22 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

tilings and in an ideal world. Aristotle taught that forms ex- 
isted in things but were distinct from matter. The Chris- 
tians taught that ideas or forms existed in the mind of 
God and moulded matter into things of the universe. 

All these philosophers Lave been called "realists" since 
they taught that ideas or forms are real things existing in- 
dependently of whether or not they ever come in contact 
with matter. In each instance the idea or form could exist 
without matter. 

But there arose a thinker wlio dared to fling himself in 
the teeth of all this tradition and to declare that these ideas 
or forms, these "universal** as they were called, were mere 
names and had no reality. His name was ROSCELIN, or 
sometimes called Roscellinus. He taught that the only real 
things are the individual objects in the universe. Each in- 
dividual man exists, but the universal ^mankind* does not 
exist at all. It is merely a name for a collection of men. 

You can see easily that Roscelin and the great philo- 
sophic tradition were directly opposed to each other. The 
result was a long and bitter dispute between the Realists, 
or those who believed that universals were real, and the 
"Nominalists/* who taught that universals were mere 
names and had no real existence. This dispute was very 
important since it was a fight over the question as to 
whether the things of nature, the objects of the universe, 
are real or merely copies of real things. It was an attempt 
to answer the question: What is real, the world which we 
can experience with our senses or the world which we 
think with our minds? 

ANSEXM, the Archbishop of Canterbury during a good 
bit of the eleventh century, was on the side of the Realists. 
He believed that these "reals," ideas or forms, existed in- 
dependently of any individual obj'ect. Mankind, for him, 
was a real thing which existed over and above any one 
man. He, along with PETER ABELARD, BERNARD OF CHAB- 
TRES, and other members of the School of Chartres, taught 
that universals or general concepts were ideas or forms hav- 
ing a separate existence and, in some way, the things which 
mould matter into individual objects which we see and ex- 



THE NATUBE OF THE UNIVERSE 23 

perience through our senses. They were all in the tradition 
of the Realists. 

These philosophers who attempted to reconcile the be- 
liefs of the Christian church and the ideas which had come 
down to them from die Greeks,-the philosophies of Plato, 
Aristotle, and others, were known as "Schoolmen," and 
the philosophies which they developed were in general 
called "Scholasticism." In every case the philosopher was 
a loyal member of the Christian church and believed the 
doctrines of the church without serious question. But most 
of them wanted to show that these doctrines were reason- 
able and could be justified by the mind of man. 

The greatest of these Schoolmen, and the one who 
worked out the relationship between Christian beliefs and 
forms of Greek philosophy, was THOMAS AQUINAS. Saint 
Thomas Aquinas, as he was later called, was born near 
Naples and lived during the thirteenth century. His great 
ambition was to show that the universe was reasonable. 
But he was one of the Realists, and endeavored to show 
that universals were real. These universals, he argued, exist 
in particular objects, in things, in such a way as to make 
them what they are. The real thing about a tree, for ex- 
ample, is not its bark, its leaves, its height, and the like. 
These are qualities in which each tree differs from other 
trees. That which makes a tree a tree is its "treeness," and 
this is a universal. This universal exists in each particular 
tree. 

But, agreeing with the Christian tradition, he held that 
all universals existed in the mind of God. 

To explain the world which we experience through our 
senses, Saint Thomas followed Aristotle in introducing mat- 
ter as that upon which universals work. Nature, for him, 
was a union of universals and matter. It is matter which 
makes one tree different from another. All trees contain the 
universal "treeness," but they differ, they are elms, oaks, 
spruces, tall, short, green, red, and the like, because of the 
different amounts of matter which each contains. All the 
universe, then, is a result of the coming together of matter 



24 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

and universals, and the many things in the universe differ 
in the amount of matter which they contain. 

For Saint Thomas, God created the world out of nothing. 
He was the cause of both matter and the universals. Fur- 
ther, God is continually creating the world as he brings 
universals and matter together to produce new objects. 
Thus, all creation did not happen at one time, but creation 
is going on all the time and all about us. 

The Schoolmen, as we have seen, were attempting to 
show that the beliefs of the church and the best thought of 
the philosophers were in agreement. In this they opened 
the door to those who would take a different position, who 
would argue that the two were in no real harmony. As soon 
as men began to study Christian beliefs and the philosophy 
of Aristotle, for example, and put them side by side, there 
were some who believed they saw contradictions. Thus 
they felt forced to choose sides. In such instances most of 
the loyal Christians sided with the church. But there were 
those who were not sure that the church was always right* 
Gradually they began to question the beliefs of the church 
and ta look about for other material which might help 
them. In this way there arose a group of thinkers who ac- 
cepted the beliefs of the church only if they could be justi- 
fied by reason. Those beliefs which they could not justify, 
they discarded as false. With the coming of these men the 
period known as Scholasticism began to fade and a new 
period to dawn. 

JOHN DUNS Scorus, a monk of the order of Saint Fran- 
cis, attempted to stem this tide of questioning and to main- 
tain the doctrines and beliefs of the Church at all cost. He 
taught, along with Saint Thomas and others, that univer- 
sal existed before things in God's mind, as forms or ideas 
in the divine mind. When things came into being, ideas or 
universals existed in them, making them what they are. 
Further, when things are not present; universals exist in 
our minds as concepts or ideas which apply to all things of 
the same kind, all trees, for example. 

For Scotus the individual object, the tree which you see, 
is different from all other trees because of its "individu- 



TEDS NATOTE OF THE UNIVERSE ^5 

ality/* not because of the amount of matter which it con- 
tains, as St. Thomas had argued. Man, argued Scotus, is 
different from an animal because there has been added 
specific differences, humanity. Both man and animals 
have life. When humanity is added to life we have man. 
Now Socrates is a man, like all other men in many respects. 
He is alive and he is distinguished from animals in that he 
has humanity. But Socrates is different from all other men. 
This difference is due, Scotus argued, to his individual 
character or individual difference. So, all things differ from 
all others because of their individuality. 

And everything in the universe is a result of the union of 
form and matter. Matter is common to all things. God 
alone is pure spirit without matter, God is form not touched 
by matter. All else is both matter and form combined. 

Although there was some opposition, the Realists were 
in command of philosophy throughout a good bit of Scho- 
lasticism. Near the beginning of the Scholastic movement, 
Roscelin, as we have seen, questioned the theory that uni- 
versals are real existences. Now, many years later, there 
arose a concerted movement to deny the reality of uni- 
versals. The leader of this movement was WILLIAM OF OC- 
CAM, an English thinker of the thirteenth century. 

William taught that particular objects and things were 
tie only realities* This world which we see and experience 
is real. Ideas, concepts, universals are mere thoughts in the 
mind, abstractions which the mind makes. They have no 
other reality. It was this position which was called "Nomi- 
nalism.* 

The universe, for the Nominalists, is composed of indi- 
vidual objects, each a thing in itself. We can see how these 
objects differ and in what ways they are alike, and can 
draw conclusions about them. But these conclusions are 
mere ideas in the mind. 

Thus, there developed two great theories about the na- 
ture of the universe. One, following the tradition which 
was begun by Plato and Aristotle, held that forms, ideas, 
universals, were real things existing either apart from ob- 
jects or in them and in some way determining what they 



6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

are. This tradition taught that the real things of tie uni- 
verse are not the individual objects of our experience, but 
the universals, the forms which determine likenesses; the 
tree which you see is not real, but the universal "tree* of 
which all trees are copies is the real thing. The other theory 
of the nature of the universe taught that the real things in 
the universe are the individual objects which we experi- 
ence, and that universals are mere thoughts in the mind. 

Hie first tradition has been that in which religion has 
flourished. The second tradition is the basis for all modern 
science. 

MEISTER ECKHART, a German mystic of the thirteenth 
century, held that God is the home of eternal ideas just as 
the artist is the home of ideas which may later become 
works of art. The world which we experience, this world of 
creatures and things, is a copy of the ideas which are in 
God. This world God created out of nothing. He, of course, 
is in the realist tradition but with an emphasis upon mys- 
ticism (which is the belief that God is all and man can 
find salvation only as he loses himself in God) . 

When the Christian church became interested in mak- 
ing its beliefs reasonable, it turned to the philosophy of 
Plato. Here the doctrine of a world of ideas distinct from 
the world of things fitted nicely into the Christian belief in 
a God who created the world out of nothing and remained 
distinct from the world. Ideas and matter were distinct in 
both Plato's philosophy and in the doctrines of the Chris- 
tian church. The great Schoolmen, who sought to make 
religion reasonable, made much use of Plato. 

But, as we have seen, there were thinkers who were not 
satisfied. They leaned toward Aristotle in holding that the 
form of an object is in some way in the object and not dis- 
tinct from it. Matter and form are combined to form things 
which we experience. They did attempt to fit God into the 
picture, but were never wholly successful. Forms, they 
held, were in things and also in the mind of God. But bow 
could they be in both places? This they never could answer 
clearly. 

Thus, there arose philosophers who became interested 



THE NATXJBE OF THE UNIVERSE &J 

in things and in their study. Some denied that the beliefs 
of the church could be made reasonable. They held that 
there were two kinds of truth, that of the church and that 
of philosophy. One may deny the other, but we should be- 
lieve both. We should accept the doctrines of the church 
by faith and the doctrines of philosophy by reason. This 
was, of course, a denial of the attempt of the Schoolmen to 
reconcile the doctrines of the church and philosophy. 

As Aristotle became more prominent in the thinking of 
Schoolmen, heresies began to develop. Philosophers came 
forward to propose that ideas or forms were not existent, 
and that the only real things are objects, individuals. Thus 
Nominalism grew out of an increasing interest in Aristotle, 
but came eventually to deny Aristotle's doctrine of forms. 
In this way Aristotle lead to the disintegration of Scholas- 
ticism and the growing concern of thinkers with the world 
of experience. The world was ready for an entirely new 
approach to the problem of the nature of the universe. 

The Views of the Forerunners of the Renaissance 

But the thinkers who tended toward a new approach 
moved slowly. After all, they were children of their times 
and the influence of the church was strong upon them. 
Thus, the early philosophers of this movement exhibited a 
strange mixture of the old and the new. 

NICHOLAS OF CUSA taught that the universe is God di- 
vided into small bits. If we think of the universe as a 
whole, all of it put together, we find that it is God. But 
each part is a part of God and God is in each thing. 

LUBOVICO VIVES, a Spaniard of this period the sixteenth 
century-taught that we should stop trying to learn about 
the world by reading what others'in the past had written 
and should go out and study nature, observe the world 
about us, and make experiments to discover how it is made. 
He was typical of those philosophers who wanted to turn 
away from the theories of the past and study the universe 
as it is experienced. In this way, they believed, man could 
learn the real nature of the universe. 

As philosophers became more interested in the study of 



28 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

nature they sought to understand it and gain power over 
it. Of course, they did not have our modern instruments or 
our modern knowledge. They stood on the threshold of the 
modern world Thus, they sought short cuts to these goals. 
The result was a form of magic, a belief that the secrets of 
the universe could be understood if one had the right se- 
cret word to utter or the correct magical act to perform. 
Thus there arose Alchemy, an attempt to make gold out of 
baser metals, Astrology, a belief that the movements of 
the stars determined man's life and all of nature, and many 
other strange doctrines. 

PARACELSUS, for example, taught that man possessed 
two bodies and a soul. The visible body comes from the 
earth, the invisible body comes from the stars, and the soul 
comes from God. He believed that there were three basic 
substances: sal (the principle of all solids), mercury (the 
principle of all liquids), and sulphur (the combustible). 
Each of these elements is ruled by spirits. To control na- 
ture one must control these spirits. AH nature is the home 
of strange spirits which must be handled by magic acts 
and words. 

Other philosophers followed in this line, seeking to ac- 
count for the universe as the home of many spirits. But, 
gradually there arose thinkers who threw off this mass of 
superstition and began to look at the world as a place 
where forces met and opposed each other, BERNARDINO 
TELESIO taught that tie universe is made up of matter and 
force. Matter is created by God and remains constant all 
the time. Heat is a force which expands matter, and cold 
is a force which contracts matter. Thus, all objects in the 
universe are, for him, a result of either expansion or con- 
traction of matter. 

In time men were able to move beyond the strange 
magical theories of their predecessors and study nature as 
the result of moving bodies. As they did this, they saw how 
bodies moved in certain definite ways. This observation 
lead to the statement of certain laws of the universe. 

GALILEO was influenced by the theories of Democritus, 
and believed that all change in the universe is due to the 



THE NATCBE OF THE "UNIVERSE &Q 

movement of parts or atoms. He developed his thinking 
along mathematical lines and attempted to show that the 
entire tiniverse was mathematical. His work, along with 
that of Kepler, established the belief that the sun and not 
the earth is the center of the universe. This is known as 
the Copemican or heliocentric theory of the universe. With 
the coming of SIR ISAAC NEWTON, fhfe theory was proved 
beyond tie shadow of a doubt, so that today we recognize 
that the sun is the center of our universe and all the 
planets move about it in very definite ways. 

GIORDANO BRUNO, writing in the spirit of the new age, 
conceived the universe as composed of numerous uncaused 
and wholly imperishable parts which he called "monads * 
These parts unite to form bodies and things in various 
ways. Further, the universe is the result of the union of 
form and matter, much as Aristotle had held. Change re- 
sults from matter taking on new f onru Particular objects, 
therefore, may change. But this is only change of parts; 
the whole, the universe, remains constant 

TOMMASO GAMPANKLLA, another early philosopher of 
this new age, held that nature is a revelation of God. The 
world is the result of emanations from God. God produced 
angels, ideas, spirits, immortal human souls, space, and 
bodies. Thus, the universe is a result of God's creative 
activity. 

The Universe According to the Philosophers 
of the Renaissance 

FRANCIS BACON lived during the sixteenth and early 
part of the seventeenth centuries. Although he did not con- 
struct a theory of the universe, as "trumpeter of his time" 
he laid the foundation for a modern theory. Bacon com- 
pletely separated religion and philosophy. He argued that 
the doctrines of religion could not be proved by thinking 
and that men should give up the attempt; that to try was 
a great waste of time and energy. 

Having relegated the doctrines of religion to a realm all 
their own, Bacon set about to develop a method of think- 
ing which he believed would give mankind true knowledge 



30 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

about his universe. This method we speak of as "induc- 
tion." By careful study of the likenesses and differences 
among things, man could discover the laws, causes, or 
"forms" of objects in the universe. In this way he would 
come to understand the universe. 

For Bacon, nothing exists in the universe save individual 
bodies. These act according to fixed laws which, if under- 
stood, serve as the keys to unlock the mysteries of the uni- 
verse and the levers by which to control this universe. In 
this Bacon had turned wholly in the direction of modern 
science and put the ancients and the Schoolmen to his back, 
He was marching forward toward the world which we 
understand today, a world of things and laws. Although he 
did not offer a complete theory of the nature of the uni- 
verse, he pointed the way which others might take in de- 
veloping such a theory. 

With THOMAS HOBBES philosophy has entered upon the 
new and modern era. Hobbes breaks completely with the 
past, with Greek philosophy and with the Schoolmen. Be- 
ing a student of mathematics, Hobbes set about to think of 
the world in terms comparable to mathematics. As a re- 
sult, his philosophy is wholly materialistic concerned with 
the material. 

Hobbes assumes dogmatically, without trying to prove 
it, that the world is a world of bodies in motion. These 
bodies are in space and have certain characteristics or "ac- 
cidents* such as motion, rest, color, hardness, and the like. 
Motion is the continuous giving up of one space by a body 
and the assuming of another. When one body affects an- 
other, it either generates an accident in the affected body 
or destroys an accident For example, let us imagine a body 
at rest Hobbes would say that this body had the accident 
of rest Now, suppose another body so affects this one that 
it is no longer at rest, but is in motion. In this case the sec- 
ond body has destroyed the accident of rest and generated 
or created the accident of motion. This is what we call the 
law of cause and effect, one accident perishes and another 
is generated. 

All objects are in motion, according to Hobbes. This mo- 



THE NATUBE OF TEE UNIVERSE 3^ 

tion was given to them by God at the creation. As bodies 
move about, they influence each other so that accidents 
are destroyed or created. 

Everything in the universe, even God, is a body (is cor- 
poreal) and is moving. Thus, with bodies and motion* 
Hobbes conceives the entire universe. This is why his phi- 
losophy is spoken of as materialistic. 

Descartes 9 Conception of the Universe 

REN DESCARTES was also a mathematician. His study 
of this subject and his respect for its certainty made him 
seek to build a philosophy which would be as certain as 
mathematics. He decided very early in his career that 
everything in nature must be explained mechanically, with- 
out the aid of forms, ideas, universal^. Thus, his whole phi- 
losophy is machine-like, mechanistic. 

At tie base of everything in the universe, of aH bodies, 
is substance, he wrote. Substance is that which exists by 
itself and independently of anything else. There are, he 
believed, two kinds of substance, mind and body. These 
exist independently of each other, but both depend upon 
God who is the only absolute substance. 

The substance that is body has the attribute of exten- 
sionthat is, it has length, breadth, and thickness. This 
body substance expresses itself in many modes, many in- 
dividual objects in the universe. Therefore, every thing in 
the universe is a mode of the substance which is body. 
And each thing stems back to God, the absolute substance. 

Further, in the universe there is no empty space or vac- 
uum. Bodies fill all space. And bodies can be divided in- 
finitely, into smaller and smaller particles. 

Everything that goes on in the universe, according to 
Descartes, is in some way a modification of extension. Ex- 
tension may be divided into an infinite number of particles 
which may be united into different forms of matter. 

Motion causes bodies to pass from one place to another. 
Motion, then, is a mode of movable things. All that hap- 
pens in the universe is the transference of motion from one 
part of space to another. But the motion in the universe 



JJ2 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

is constant At the beginning God gave the world a certain 
definite amount of motion. Thus motion remains the same 
in the universe; it cannot be destroyed. If one object 
slows up, another must move faster. 

Further, according to Descartes, all change in the world 
must take place according to laws. Indeed, all the laws of 
nature are, in the philosophy of Descartes, laws of motion. 

The universe, then, is composed of bodies created by 
God and endowed with motion. These bodies move about 
according to fixed and purely mechanical laws. As we 
learn these laws, we can understand the universe and come 
to control it. This is a purely mechanical theory of organic 
nature. It contains no forms or ideas, no universals. 

Mind, which we shall discuss in more detail in a later 
chapter, is for Descartes also a substance. Its attribute is 
thinking, and it expresses itself in many modes. Although 
body and mind are both substances, and both stem from 
God, they are independent To maintain this complete in- 
dependence, Descartes gave himself the most difficult 
problem of showing how mind can influence body or body 
influence mind. His solution of this problem will be dis- 
cussed when we come to the study of mind and matter. 

The great merit of Descartes' philosophy was, however, 
this extreme separation of body and mind. We may speak 
of his thought as emphasizing the "dualism" of mind and 
matter; that is, stressing the "two-f old" nature of the uni- 
verse. By making these two substances entirely independ- 
ent, he left nature free for the mechanical explanations of 
natural science. The scientists could busy themselves with 
a study of nature without having to worry about mind. 
Science could develop along purely mechanical lines with- 
out having to make room for purposes, goals, and other 
characteristics of mind or spirit. It could busy itself with 
the discovery of the laws by which all bodies act and move. 
Indeed, in this way modern science was made possible. 

This dualism of Descartes brought to the fore the prob- 
lem of how we can know anything about the material 
world. How can mind, which is absolutely distinct from 
matter, know a material world? How can we answer any 



THE NATUKE OP THE TOTTVERSE 33 

of the questions about the nature of the universe? ABNOLD 
GCTXINCX, a successor of Descartes, teaches that God 
alone has knowledge of things, and all that we can know 
is ourselves* NICOLAS MALEBBANCHE, another thinker of 
the period following Descartes, agreed with Guelincx that 
we cannot know anything about the universe. However, 
we <3o have ideas about the world, we think we see it, and 
experience it in many ways. And we act accordingly. But 
all we have are ideas which God has put in us. *Tf God," 
he writes, Tiad destroyed the created world, and would 
continue to affect me as he now affects me, I should con- 
tinue to see what I now see." Thus, the universe which 
we experience is a universe of ideas. Whether or not there 
is a material world "out there," we cannot know. 

Consequently, by making a sharp distinction between 
the material and the mental, Descartes opened the door to 
complete skepticism as regards the existence of a universe 
outside of the human mind. And many thinkers entered 
this door and denied the existence of such a world. If 
mind and matter are distinct, then neither can influence 
the other, and mind cannot know matter, the world of 
things. 

Spinoza's Theory of the Universe 

Descartes, as we have seen, taught that the universe is 
made up of two kinds of substance, mind and body. This 
dualism did not satisfy BENEDICT SPINOZA. Spinoza taught 
that there is only one substance, one basic "stuff* which 
constitutes the entire universe. This he called God. For 
Spinoza, everything in the universe is God, and all the 
individual things are actually one great whole. 

We may think of the basic substance as, for example, a 
great metal shield, with different designs on each side. If 
we look at It from one side we see a definite design, but if 
we look at it from the other side we see a wholly different 
design. So with substance. If it is seen in one way it is 
body. If seen from another position it is mind. Spinoza 
called the one extension and the other mind. 

Thus, every object in the universe, star, tree, man, ani- 



34 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

mal, water, wind, stone, is a part of God, is God. Every 
object is also both extension and mind. There is no body 
without mind and no mind without body. 

Substance, the underlying "stuff" of the universe, is ab- 
solutely independent of everything, for it is everything. It 
is infinite, self -caused, and self-determined. It has no limits, 
was made by itself, and is determined by nothing but it- 
self. This God, or Nature, is the world. This unifying con- 
ception is known as "pantheism." So thorough is Spinoza 
in holding this position that he has been referred to as 
"God-intoxicated." 

This substance, God, expresses itself in an infinite num- 
ber of attributes, but man can grasp only two, extension 
and thought. God, or Nature, is both body and mind. Fur- 
ther, these attributes are absolutely independent of each 
other. Body does not affect mind nor does mind affect 
body. But both are manifestations of one and the same 
universal reality, God. 

These attributes appear to man in specific ways or 
"modes.** There are many bodies and many ideas. The 
particular body, a tree, is a mode .of extension which is an 
attribute of God, My particular thought at this moment 
is a mode of mind which is an attribute of God. 

All the bodies in the universe and all the ideas grouped 
together form a totality which is God or substance. This 
constitutes the "face of the whole universe." The individual 
objects or ideas may change, but the whole, the "face of 
the whole universe," does not change. 

Further, all the bodies in the universe form a chain of 
causes. The tree you see was caused by something else, 
which in turn was caused by something else, and so on. 
Thus tiiis particular tree owes its existence to some other 
physical object. It is not necessary that God create this 
tree; but, having it present, he is the underlying substance 
of it. If, for example, we have a triangle, we know im- 
mediately that certain things must be true of it. It has 
certain properties, and all triangles will have these prop- 
erties. However, we cannot tell from the concept of a 
triangle the number, size, and shape of different triangles. 



THE NATUBJE CF THE UNIVEBSE 35 

In the same way, from substance we can state the prop- 
erties of bodies, but we cannot state the properties of the 
different objects in the universe. 

For Spinoza, then, the entire universe is one substance, 
which he called God or Nature. This substance has at 
least two attributes, extension and mind. And there are 
many modes of each attribute. Thus, God is the universe 
and the universe is God. But bodies are independent of 
mind and mind is independent of body. However, when 
something happens in body, it also happens in mind. This 
is called "psycho-physical parallelism"; that is, body and 
mind are always parallel, for they are two aspects of one 
and the same substance. 

The Positions of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume 

JOHN LOCKE, admirer of Descartes but thinker who gave 
to the modern world a new interpretation of man, began 
his thinking with the question: How does man know? His 
conclusion, after a long and painstaking investigation, was 
that all knowledge comes from sense impressions. This 
point of view made it necessary for him to account for the 
universe as the source of these impressions. 

Is there a real world which corresponds to our ideas? If 
there is such a world, how can we, having only ideas, 
prove its existence? Locke's answer was to the effect that 
there is such a world. Our senses, he said, tell us of this 
world. We do experience this world and are justified in 
saying that it exists. Though we may not be able to say 
much about the source of our sensations, we are able to 
say that the sensations are caused. Thus, the real world is 
the cause of our sensations. This much we can say. For 
example, we have an idea of white. This idea is not born in 
us, but is caused. From this we can reason that the real 
world contains something which causes in us an idea of 
white. 

However, even of this we cannot be absolutely certain. 
Our knowledge of this world is probable. We can be more 
certain of the existence in the universe of ourselves and of 



36 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

God. But all else is only probable. Therefore, Locke ar- 
gued, we can never have a perfect natural science. 

At tiiis point Locke follows fairly closely the position of 
Descartes, which we have outlined. The world, he holds, 
is composed of substances. These are the bases, the sup- 
ports, of all qualities. We experience, for example, white. 
This quality just does not float around in space, but is the 
whiteness of something. This something is a substance. 

Further, there are two kinds of substances, bodies and 
souls. Bodies have the attributes of extension, solidity, and 
impenetrability. They fill space, are solid, and cannot be 
penetrated. Souls are spiritual substances, are immaterial. 
Souls, mincfe, and bodies act upon each other. The body 
can cause happenings in the soul, and what happens to 
the soul may affect the body. For example, bodies act 
upon the mind so that we have experiences of color, sound, 
touch, and the like. Despite his belief in interaction, 
Locke's theory of the universe is dualistic. There are minds 
and there are bodies. While both are substances, they are 
different kinds of substances. 

Here it is evident that, with some changes, Locke follows 
in the footsteps of Descartes in holding that bodies and 
mind are two kinds of substances, or bearers of qualities. 
The universe is made up of these substances. However, we 
can know only the ideas which these substances produce in 
us through sensations. 

If, however, the basis of knowledge is sensation and re- 
flection upon sensations, how can we know that a world 
of bodies distinct from our ideas of bodies exists? GEORGE 
BERKELEY asked this question. John Locke had taught that, 
actually, all we can know are our Ideas, and had presup- 
posed a world which causes our sensations. But Berkeley 
recognized immediately that he could not prove the exist- 
ence of such a world on the basis of his philosophy. Fur- 
ther, Berkeley, being a deeply religious man and seeing 
so much atheism or disbelief in God in the world, was 
convinced that atheism would be abolished if one could 
disprove belief in matter. 

Consequently, Berkeley carried Locke's philosophy to its 



THE NATDBE OF THE UNIVERSE 37 

logical conclusion as he saw it, and taught that there can 
be no universe of material objects. All we can prove, he 
argued, is that we have ideas. 

But what about the source of these ideas? Do we create 
our own ideas? Berkeley answered, "No/* The cause of 
sensations, and thus the cause of all ideas, is God. We 
cannot perceive God but can perceive the effects of his 
work, ideas. 

Berkeley held consistently, as he believed, to the position 
that nothing in the universe existed unless it was perceived. 
I am sitting in my room. I look about and see chairs, a 
table, books, and other objects. These are not real in the 
sense that they are material objects. They are ideas in my 
mind. But, if I leave the room, do these objects vanish? 
Do I carry them out of the room in my mind? Berkeley 
taught that they might still exist in some other mind. If 
other people are in the room, they may exist in their minds. 
If there are no other people in the room, they may still 
exist in the mind of God. But, all the time, they are ideas 
and not material objects. 

The material universe, which Descartes, Spinoza, and 
Locke had taught existed, was denied by Berkeley. For 
him, all that exists are ideas in the mind. If they are not in 
my mind, they may be in your mind or in God's mind. Of 
course, they seem to be material, but actually they are not. 
Berkeley was simply following the ideas of Locke to their 
logical conclusion, to a denial of the existence of a material 
universe. 

DAVID HUME, a Scot of the eighteenth century, felt that 
Berkeley had not gone far enough. Not only must we 
abandon the idea of substance, he taught, but we must 
also abandon the idea of a God in whose mind all ideas 
exist. Hume could find no good argument for the existence 
of God. 

Then, all that we have is a succession of ideas. These 
are caused by impressions. Hume agreed with Berkeley 
that only those things exist which are perceived. My table 
exists only when it is perceived. I may perceive it, my 
friend may perceive it, or God may perceive it. Thus, "to 



38 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

be is to be perceived.* However, we cannot prove fiat 
God exists. Therefore, if I am in a room alone and per- 
ceive a table, the table exists as I perceive it When I 
leave the room, the table no longer exists. 

There is, then, in Hume's view, no substance. All that 
we have is a succession, a stream of ideas, one following 
the other. We cannot prove the cause, of these ideas. It is 
foolish to say that there is a substance "out there" in space 
causing our ideas. No one can prove this. Whenever we 
look, we find ideas following each other, ideas of chairs, 
tables, people, trees, stars, and the like. Thus we have no 
evidence of the existence of a world of nature or of God. 

Hume carried Locke's theory to its logical and final con- 
clusion in skepticism* Locke had taught that we have ideas 
which are caused by an outer world, Hume admitted the 
existence of ideas, but showed that, if this is all we have, 
we are shut up |n our own minds and cannot prove the 
existence of an outside world. All we can be sure of is a 
parade of individual ideas, one following the other. Their 
cause, their connection, even the place where they are 
parading is unknown. We have come in Hume to a dead- 
end street. 

It is natural that man would not remain satisfied with 
the skepticism of Hume. THOMAS KEID, another Scot, led 
the opposition. He taught that Hume had reached an im- 
possible position. Common sense tells us that a real world 
exists as the cause of our sensations and ideas. We may 
speculate all we want, but we will not be contented to deny 
what common sense tells us. Therefore, he argues, those 
things which we perceive distinctly by our senses exist, 
and they exist as we perceive them. There is a world "out 
there** corresponding to our ideas. Tables, chairs, and the 
like do exist independently of our ideas of them. Common 
sense tells us that this is so, and we cannot deny common 
sense. 

German thought took a different road from that of Eng- 
land or Scotland. It was concerned with the then develop- 
ing natural sciences, but found itself believing in the values 
of Christian beliefs. Consequently, it sought to reconcile 



THE NATURE OF THE UNIVERSE 39 

science and these valuable elements in Christian specu- 
lation. 

Leibnittf Theory of the Universe 

GOTTFBIED WILHELM LEIBNITZ, one of the leaders of 
German thought in the seventeenth century, became con- 
vinced after much careful study and investigation that the 
essential attribute of the bodies in the universe is force. 
By force he meant "the tendency of the body to move or 
continue its motion.* The entire universe is, for "him, built 
out of units of force. Each body consists of a number of 
these units of force, and all nature consists of an infinite 
number of such units. These units of force Leibnitz called 
"monads/' or force-atoms. Each monad is eternal, it cannot 
be destroyed or changed. 

But monads have different degrees of clearness. The 
most obscure, vague, cloudy monads form plants. Those 
less cloudy form animals. The monads which form man 
are still clearer. And the clearest of all monads is God. 
The universe is composed of an infinite number of monads 
extending all the way from the most cloudy monad to 
God, There is no break in this series. At one extreme is 
inorganic matter, rocks and the like. And at the other ex- 
treme is God. 

Each monad contains within itself the entire universe. 
Thus, since the monad has no "windows," all that it be- 
comes is contained within it from the beginning. Each 
monad realizes its nature with an inner necessity. Nothing 
can be in a monad but what has been there from the 
beginning. 

The organic bodies, living beings, contain a "queen 
monad" or soul which is the guiding principle of all the 
monads which make up the body. No monad can influence 
another. God created monads in the beginning so that they 
operate together in harmony. When one monad does some- 
thing, it does not influence another monad. But, because 
the other monad is so created, it acts as though the one 
had influenced it. Thus all monads act together just as do 
the various parts of an organism. 



40 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Leibnitzf universe, then, is not mechanical, but is dy- 
namic, alive. It is composed of an infinite number of mon* 
ads of various degrees of clearness. Here we sense the old 
theory of Democritus, the atomistic theory. But the atoms 
of Leibnitz are not all alike, nor are they pure mechanical 
units. They are units of force and differ in clearness. And 
God is the clearest monad. 

By means of this theory, Leibnitz believed that he had 
reconciled the science of his day with the values of the 
Christian doctrine. He had a scientific universe in which 
God was the supreme being or monad. 

Kant's Conception of the Universe 

German philosophy reached its height in the worlc of 
IMMANCEL KANT, one of the great philosophic system- 
builders of all times. His fundamental problem lay in the 
question, What is knowledge, and how is it possible? What 
can we really know, and how? His conclusion was that we 
can know only our experiences* We have sensations. We 
see a chair. Because our minds are such as they are, we 
receive this sensation in a definite way. But we cannot 
know the cause of the sensation. 

On this theory, we cannot know the universe which 
exists outside of our fhtiVlrfng, Our ?nfnj$ receive sensa- 
tions and shape them into ideas because they are what 
they are. What the world is without our minds, it is im- 
possible for us to know. 

But, by Reason we can form an Idea of this world, this 
universe. As we experience the world in our minds, we 
find that the world has no beginning in time, that bodies 
in the world cannot be divided infinitely, that everything 
in the world takes place according to the laws of nature, 
and that there is no absolutely necessary Being who causes 
the world to -be. We must accept this theory of the world 
of experience because we cannot experience it otherwise. 

However, Reason can construct a world of Idea which 
has no beginning in time, in which bodies can be divided 
infinitely, in which there is freedom, and in which there is 
an absolutely necessary Being, God, who is the cause of 



THE NATUBE OF THE UNIVERSE 4! 

everything. Although we cannot know such a universe 
through experience, we can reason its existence and we can 
act as though it were real. Indeed, Kant believed that man 
must act as though this kind of a world existed if he would 
preserve his moral integrity. For, on the basis of such a 
world Kant reasoned to the existence of God, freedom, and 
immortality. Further, he showed that all goodness, all mo- 
rality, was dependent upon acting as if this land of a world 
existed. The Idea of this world, he held, is regulative, it 
directs man to certain goals. Believing in the eixstence of 
such a universe, man strives to be good. 

Thus, for Kant, there are two universes: one of experi- 
ence, the "phenomenal" world, and one of reason, the 
"noumenal" world. The one is scientific, the other is 
practical. 

Kant taught that the fundamental principle of the prac- 
tical world is a moral law which may be stated: "Always 
act so that you can will the maxim or determining principle 
of your action to become universal law; act so that you can 
will that everybody shall follow the principle of your ac- 
tion." This he called the "categorical imperative." 

If one is to act so that the principle of his action shall be- 
come a law for all men, he must be free to act in this way. 
Therefore, Kant placed freedom at the center of his prac- 
tical world. We shall discuss Kant's view of the practical 
world more fully in our chapter on "What Is Good and 
.WhatlsEvil?" 

Fickte, Schetting, and Hegel 

JOHANN GOTTLIEB FICHTE took this principle of freedom 
and made it fundamental to his whole philosophical posi- 
tion. He took the stand that the self, the "ego," is a free, 
self-determining activity. 

The starting-point of Fichte's thinking is this ego or 
creative, free principle. It is God, and is the creator of all 
that is. It creates each individual person, you and me and 
all the individuals in the universe. It also creates the entire 
world of things. 

But, we and all things are not matter, material. There is 



42 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

no material in the sense of lifeless matter such as the 
older philosophers taught Everything in the universe is 
spirit The tree and your mind are both the universal, ab- 
solute ego or God. Thus, the real world is a world of mind 
or spirit and not a world of dead matter. Everything is the 
ego, God. But the ego creates a limit to itself so that it 
may contend against this limit and grow to perfection. 
Thus, the world of objects, the so-called "material" world, 
is produced by the ego to furnish an arena in which it may 
exercise its freedom. 

Freedom would mean nothing if there were not some- 
thing hindering the exercise of freedom. Therefore, the 
eternal ego, God, has created the world, the "non-ego," as 
a limit to itself, a world of opposition in which it can 
struggle, in which it can become conscious of itself. This 
is a world of law, a world in which things happen ac- 
cording to set rules. 

My reason, your reason, our minds are also creations or 
parts of this universal ego. We do not create our world of 
things, but are creations of the same ego which has created 
this world. Since the universal ego is the universal active 
reason, the same in all persons, we all see the world alike. 

This point of view is called "Idealism." It is based upon 
the belief that there is no matter in the universe, but every- 
thing is mind or spirit, idea. Descartes, Locke, and even 
Kant had taught that there are two principles in the uni- 
verse, mind and matter. Fichte denied this recognition of 
two principles. He eliminated matter, and held that every- 
thing in the universe is mind or spirit The world only 
seems to be material. If we understand aright, we shall 
realize that even this is spirit. The universe is mind, spirit, 
ego, God. Thus, though the universe is a reality outside of 
individual personal minds, it is not made of a different ma- 
terial, it is not a world of dead things. But, it is "the revela- 
tion in human consciousness of the absolute principle/' Na- 
ture is spirit, mind, and can be nothing else. 

Thus, for Fichte, the moral law of Kant implies freedom, 
freedom implies deliverance from obstacles. There must be 
obstacles. Therefore, the universal self or ego created out 



THE NATURE OF THE TXNIVEBSE 43 

of itself the world of sensible things to serve as its op- 
ponent. The world of experience is deduced from the moral 
law. Because this concept of Kant's influenced Fichte and 
many other thinkers, we speak of Kant as the father of 
modern Idealism* 

Following in this same idealistic tradition was FKDEDBICH 
Wn.HFXM JOSEPH SCHELUNG, brilliant German philoso- 
pher and student of religion. For hfm, as for Fichte, the 
ground of all the universe was one all-pervading world 
spirit or ego. However, he taught that this spirit as found 
in nature was not conscious of itself, and that it became 
fully self-conscious only in man. 

Thus there is a development in consciousness from na- 
ture through man. Nature and thinking are steps or stages 
in the development of the absolute mind. God is nature and 
God is mind. The one is God asleep while the other is God 
fully awake. But, in either, or throughout the whole de- 
velopment, God remains the same. 

All the universe, including man, is a whole. The parts, 
the objects and individuals are all parts of the whole. Thus 
nature is alive, dynamic, creative. Wherever one may stop 
to investigate, he will find spirit striving to realize itself 
fully, to become wholly self-conscious. Inorganic nature, 
the trees, rocks, earth, and the like, are of tie same ma- 
terial as is the human mind. But the former are blind, 
"unripe," unconscious. 

This doctrine is pantheism. The universe is conceived as 
a living, growing, moving system. God is the universe and 
the universe is God. In plants and rocks, God is blind, 
unconscious impulse. Move upward to man and God be- 
comes conscious or seeing, he comes to knowledge of him- 
self. 

GEORG WILHELM FBIEDBICH HEGEL attempted to bring 
the philosophical positions of Kant, Fichte, and Schelling 
into a whole which would be complete and satisfying. 
Thus, he taught that the entire universe is an evolution of 
mind from nature to God. 

Everywhere, in the natural world or in the mind of man, 
we find a process of unfolding. This he called the dialec- 



44 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

tical process or the principle of contradiction. Everything 
tends to pass over to its opposite. The seed tends to become 
a flower. However, nature does not stop with these con- 
tradictions, hut strives to overcome them, to reconcile them 
in a whole or unity. 

The entire universe is a whole. In it this principle is 
working, a principle which is rational. Mind is everywhere. 
Within this whole there is development. And this develop- 
ment proceeds by the dialectical process. First we discover 
a thing, a "thesis." Then we discover its opposite or con- 
tradiction, an "antithesis/* These two are at last reconciled 
in a "synthesis" which becomes another "thesis'* and the 
process starts again. 

All the universe is a continuation of this process within 
the whole. Reality then is a process of evolution, a develop- 
ing from a less dear to a more clear. 

This process is the process of thought. Therefore, the 
universe is thought and is subject to the laws of thought. 
As we think, so the universe develops. But this is all a 
process of a thinking whole. Nature and man are one 
within this whole. The same processes which are found in 
man's mind are also found in nature. In nature this move- 
ment proceeds unconsciously. The seed grows into a plant, 
and into a flower. But it is not conscious of its growth. In 
man the process becomes conscious and man knows that he 
is developing. This same process is discovered everywhere. 

For Hegel, then, the universe is a whole or totality. 
This .whole is a thinking process and it develops as does all 
thought, thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. This is Ideal- 
ism worked out completely and to the last degree. 

The Views of the Later German Philosophers 

The idealistic philosophy of Hegel certainly could not go 
unchallenged. It contradicted so much of common sense 
that it was inevitable that a thinker, or group of thinkers, 
would arise to present the other side of the picture. 
JOHANN FRIEDRICH HERBART was such a thinker. He took 
issue with every phase of Hegel's philosophy and sought to 



THE NATURE OF THK TXNIVEBSE 45 

show that the idealistic philosophy was full of impossible 
theories. 

For Herbart the universe consists of a great number of 
unchangeable principles or substances which he called 
"reals." Each real is a simple thing, Is changeless, absolute, 
indivisible, not extended in time or in space. In the world 
of reals there is no change, no growth; it is static. 

Our bodies are aggregates of these reals, and each soul 
is a real. Each real strives to maintain itself against any- 
thing that would affect it. In this striving for self-preserva- 
tion, each real will behave differently in the presence of 
different reals. 

We relate reals together into aggregates and thus create 
the universe which we experience. For example, I come 
into relationship with many reals and bring them together 
into a red apple. Then, by bringing other reals into the 
situation and rejecting some which I had there first, the 
apple becomes a peeled apple. Thus, the real world is ab- 
solutely static. Nothing happens in it. AH happenings are 
phenomena in consciousness. As consciousness arranges 
and rearranges reals, things appear, change, and dis- 
appear. 

The entire uiSverse, then, is, for Herbart, made up of 
these spaceless, timeless, units which never change, but 
which exert activity in preserving themselves against other 
reals. As We arrange and rearrange reals we produce the 
world of experience. 

This theory of the universe is known as "Realism," and 
its basic idea is that the universe is real and is not a crea- 
tion of mind. Although experience reveals only phenom- 
ena, an appearance must always be the appearance of 
something. There is a reality which causes the appear- 
ance. Kant had called this reality the "thing-in-itself." 
Hegel had argued that there is no such "thing." Herbart 
agreed with Kant and sought to describe this real cause 
of appearances. 

ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER attacked the problem from an- 
other angle. He agreed with. Kant that the world of ex- 
perience is a world of phenomena; but he disagreed with 



46 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

him in holding that we can become aware of the thing-in- 
itself. He noted that when man wants something he sets 
about to build or create it. I want a table, and I get boards, 
tools, nails, and build one. Or I work to make the money 
to buy one. 

From this, he argued that will is the cause of all things 
in the universe. The thing-in-itself, for him, is will, the 
cause of everything. The universe is a result of will. 

In organic and inorganic life the fact is the same. In a 
rock, will is blind, but it is the creative principle which 
brings the rock into being. As we move up to man, will 
becomes conscious. Man may direct his will by intelligence 
in getting what he wills* The universe, then, is a result of 
will, a primal will which continues to work regardless of 
the coming or going of individuals. 

RUDOLF HERMANN LOTZE sought to interpret Kant's 
thing-in-itself in terms of mind. He taught that the physical 
world is to be understood as purely mechanical, as a mat- 
ter of physical and chemical laws. But, this is the world of 
perception. The cause of this world is comparable to soul 
or mind. 

Thus, there are various degrees of reality. In the case of 
matter mental life is present but clouded. In man this 
mental life is conscious and dear. The universe, then, is 
alive and is mind. Here again we encounter Idealism. 

The work of Lotze and other Idealists made a profound 
impression on the thinking of their age. GUSTAV THEODOR 
FECHNER conceived the universe as similar to human in- 
dividuals. The material world is the body of the universe. 
But this body has a soul or a mental life. This mental life 
is to be found in descending degrees in animals, plants, 
and lastly in organic matter. God is the soul of the uni- 
verse, just as the human body has a soul. FRIEDRICH PAUL- 
SEN and WILHELM WUNDT followed in the same tradition. 
Wundt taught that the external world is "the outer husk 
behind which lies concealed a spiritual creation, a striving 
and feeling reality resembling that which we experience 
in ourselves." 

By admitting the existence of a material world they met 



THE NATUBE OF THE "UNIVERSE 47 

the objections of those who felt that the Idealists had 
denied common sense* But, hy holding that mind or spirit 
is the creative spirit in this world, that the world is alive, 
they believed tibat they had conserved the values of Ideal- 
ism. Their philosophies were attempts to meet the de- 
mands of the then growing natural sciences while at the 
same time to escape the crass materialism which threat- 
ened philosophy as science became stronger. They be- 
lieved that the values of mind, spirit, or soul should not 
be covered up and lost completely in the landslide of 
modern science. 

The Positions of John Stuart Mitt and Herbert Spencer 

JOHN STCJART MILL taught that actually our ideas are all 
that we can know. We find these ideas following each other 
in consistent ways and so often that we can be reasonably 
sure that they will continue to do so. For example, the idea 
of being burned always follows the idea of sticking one's 
hand into a fire. 

Mill holds that law and order reign in the universe and 
that there are invariable sequences of events upon which 
we can depend. Further, he teaches that the law of cause 
and effect is universal. We find a certain set of ideas being 
followed in every case by the same idea. This leads us to 
recognize that the effect is caused by the set of preceding 
ideas. 

But, as is evident, up to this point Mill is discussing 
phenomena, experiences, ideas. What of the cause of these? 
Is there an external universe? Mill believes that there is 
such a universe which is the cause of our sensations. I see 
a piece of white paper in a room. Then I leave the room 
and remember that the paper was experienced under cer- 
tain conditions. I return to the room and again experience 
the paper. After I have done this several times with the 
same results, the paper is always experienced upon my re- 
turn to the room, I generalize that the paper is there in the 
external world and causes my experience. I form the no- 
tion of something permanent, persisting. Thus "the so- 
called external world is simply the possibility that certain 



48 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

sensations will recur in the same order in which they have 
occurred/* 

It is evident that Mill, although he thinks largely in the 
Idealistic tradition, believes that there is a cause of our 
sensations, experiences, a "thing-in-itself ." There is a uni- 
verse distinct from our sensations and experiences, the 
cause of ideas which we have. 

But we cannot know with absolute certainty anything 
about this world. From our experiences of it, we can be 
reasonably certain about some things in it, and not so sure 
about others. However, all that we know about it is based 
on experience, and no one has had every possible experi- 
ence so as to be able to make a generalization which will 
be without exception. There is still the possibility that some 
exception, some new experience, will arise to prove the gen- 
eralization applicable only to certain sets of conditions and 
not to others. 

HERBERT SPENCER is the great philosopher of evolution. 
He sought to develop a philosophic theory based on the 
findings of Darwin and other biologists; build a system of 
thought which would embody the important ideas of the 
doctrine of evolution. 

He began his philosophy with the recognition that phe- 
nomena, things as presented to us, are all that we can 
know. The cause of these phenomena is unknowable. But 
there is a cause, an Absolute Being behind all phenomena. 
Of course, we do make judgments about it. We conceive it 
as a force or power causing all that we know. Further, we 
think of it as both mental and physical. It is the cause of 
our thoughts and of the universe. But, all these ideas are 
mere symbols, ways which we have invented of thinking of 
the Absolute. Actually we can know nothing about it. It is 
the Unknowable. All that we can know are the inner and 
outer expressions of the Absolute. 

And these expressions obey the law of evolution. We see 
them becoming groups and these groups organizing into 
wholes. As the groups are organized, various forms of life 
evolve. The human individual is a result of the formation 
of groups of atoms into hands, arms, heart, lungs, feet, and 



THE NATUBE OF THE UNIVERSE 49 

the like, and the organization of all these into a body in 
which each part does its duty as part of the whole body. 
The legs walk, the hands grasp, the heart beats, eta 

Thus, Spencer believes in the existence of a world ex- 
ternal to our consciousness* This world we infer because it 
is impossible for us to do otherwise. Because we have im- 
pressions, we reason that there must be a cause of these 
impressions, an external world* But the impressions are not 
pictures, copies of the external world. As far as we can 
know, they may be as unlike the external world as letters 
of a word are unlike the idea which the word means, 
"H-o-r-s-e"-~ the letters themselves do not suggest the idea 
of a horse which the whole word calls before us. Likewise, 
our impressions and the actual external world may be 
wholly unlike one another. All that we can say with cer- 
tainty, Spencer believes, is that there is something beyond 
consciousness which is the cause of our impressions, the 
Unknowable, the Absolute. 

Josidh Royce, William James, and John Dewey 

JOSIAH ROYCE, leader of the Idealistic school of thought 
in the United States, began his thinking from the nature of 
man. We are conscious beings and organize our experiences 
into wholes or a system. Likewise, he teaches, the universe 
is a conscious Being, a whole. My thinking, your thinking, 
the thinking of everyone are parts of the whole thinking 
universe. 

I have an idea of a table. I do not create this idea or the 
table. The table is there. But it is not matter. Rather, the 
cause of my idea of a table is the idea of a table in the 
mind of the Absolute. It is, therefore, an idea which causes 
my idea, but is God's idea. The whole universe, then, is 
similar to my own ideas. This universe is a self-conscious 
organism idealized. It is all the ideas of all mankind and 
the causes of these ideas. The outer world is mental just 
as is the inner world of my experience. 

These thinkers, the Idealists, have attempted to inter- 
pret the universe in terms of the thinking individual in or- 
der to conserve the values of spiritual life. They have rde- 



50 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GRKAT PHILOSOPHERS 

gated science to a secondary or lower position, but have 
taken it into account For them, the laws of science are ac- 
tually the laws of thinking. But, the real world is not to be 
limited to the unchanging laws of material things. Above 
these laws are the laws of man's spirit. By this belief, they 
escape strict determinism and make possible freedom and 
morality. If man is subject to the inevitable laws of science, 
he cannot be free and it is futile to hold him to account 
for his actions. He cannot be blamed. But freedom and 
moral responsibility are too valuable to be lost in this way. 
Consequently, the Idealists hold on to them by arguing 
that the world is actually spiritual rather than physical. 
Modern science seems to them to destroy all that makes 
human life human. 

Recent philosophy is characterized by this attempt to 
take account of the whole realm of modern science with its 
laws and consistencies and at the same time preserve those 
things which men have found of value. The Idealists lay 
emphasis upon these values and think of a universe in 
which they are dominant. 

WILLIAM JAMES, one of the first Pragmatists, found that 
a "block-universe" in which everything was governed by 
the laws of science was not satisfying. He wrote, "If every- 
thing, man included, is the mere effect of the primitive 
nebula or the infinite substance, what becomes of moral re- 
sponsibility, freedom of action, individual effort, and aspira- 
tion?" He believed that the test of any theory or belief 
should be its practical consequences. This is the pragmatic 
test. And he was certain that only a theory of the universe 
which took into account moral responsibility, freedom of 
action, and the like, and made room for them, would have 
consequences that were good. 

The real world, for him, was the world of human experi- 
ence. Here we find science and human values all included. 
Beyond this he believed it impossible for a thinker to go. 
Although he did not doubt the existence of a world outside 
of experience, a world that caused experiences, he believed 
that we could not experience it and therefore could know 
nothing about it. 



THE NATURE OF THE "UNIVERSE 51 

JOHN DEWEY, one of the leaders of present-day Pragma- 
tism, held that the universe is a changing, growing, devel- 
oping thing. He concentrates his attention upon experience, 
which he finds is ever becoming, changing, being enriched. 
The philosopher, he argues, must cease to spend his time 
with questions of beginnings, of what lies outside of experi- 
ence, of a world "out there." It makes no difference for us 
whether or not there is such a world. For us it is the experi- 
ences which we have that are the important things, and the 
explanation of how they come, grow, change, and influ- 
ence other experiences. The universe of our experience is 
uncertain, doubtful, full of surprises, but is also character- 
ized by consistencies upon which we can depend. This is 
the only world in which Dewey was interested. 

The Views of Henri Bergson and George Santayana 

HENRI BERGSON, who was the leader of another attempt 
to conserve values in a world of science, taught that a uni- 
verse as described by science would not be adequate. It 
leaves out too much. To know the universe in its fullness, 
one must live in it and apprehend it by "intuition." A man 
cannot know a river by merely sitting on its banks; he must 
jump into it and swim with its current. We must immerse 
ourselves in the universe to understand it 

The universe for Bergson is a moving, growing, becom- 
ing, living thing. Science cuts a slice out of it and tells us 
that this slice is the universe. For Bergson, the slice by it- 
self is dead, unreal. The true universe is living, rich, con- 
taining the slice, but more than the slice. He characterized 
the universe as a process of "creative evolution," a becom- 
ing in which new things appear. The cause of this is the 
creative nature of the universe. "The whole evolution of 
life on our planet is an effort of this essentially creative 
force to arrive, by traversing matter, at something which 
is only realized in man and which, even in man, is realized 
only imperfectly.'* In seeking to organize matter, this crea- 
tive force has been trapped. La man, creativity is seen to be 
breaking away from matter and becoming free. 

Another modern philosopher who deals with this prob- 



52 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

lem of science and values is GEORGE SANTAYANA. His real 
universe is the universe of human experience in all its rich- 
ness and fullness. That there is a substance causing such 
experience he does not doubt, but rather seeks to justify its 
existence. He writes that Herbert Spencer was correct in 
maintaining the existence of such a substance, but believes 
that it is knowable through experience. We are certain of 
this world of experience. We find in it the kws of science 
and all the beauty, truth, and goodness for which we long, 
It is a real world in any true sense of tihie term real. 

Thus, modern science will not permit us to deny that the 
real world is as the scientist finds it, a thing upon which 
we can depend and the laws of which men can discover 
and act upon with a high degree of certainty. We can 
trust the universe as explained by the scientists. But phi- 
losophers are keenly conscious that this universe of the 
scientists is not all. They discover in the universe the hu- 
man mind, human hopes and fears, love and hate, dreams 
and defeats. Here they find men acting as though they 
were free and others holding them responsible for their ac- 
tions. The universe for them is also a place of struggle, 
planning and realization, willing and creating. It is this that 
the philosophers will not give up. 

Consequently, the universe of modern philosophy is one 
in which both science and human values are accounted for. 
Today no thinker can daim recognition unless he has in 
some way at least accounted for the discoveries of the labo- 
ratories and those of the inner man. This whole universe is 
real, and any other is but a part, and no one must hold 
that the part, any part, is the whole and the rest unreal. 
All the universe, the outer and the inner, is real, and the 
philosopher must find place for it all in his system. This is 
the problem of modern philosophy, the problem of the 
nature of the universe as seen by philosophers now writing 
and teaching. 



Chapter II 
MAN'S PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 

PROTAGORAS SOCRATES PLATO ARISTOTLE 

AUGUSTINE ABELARD AQUINAS 
SPINOZA LOCKE LEIBNITZ ROUSSEAU 

KANT NIEIZSCHE COMTE 
SPENCER JAMES DEWEY RUSSELL 



Is man the destined master of the universe, or Is he a 
"worm of the dust"? What is the relation between 
man and the universe? Is man the center of the tini- 
verse, the god of aU creation, or is he a mere inci- 
dent of no more significance to the universe than a 
speck of dust? Is the universe friendly or unfriendly to 
man, or is it merely unconcerned? 



I consider thy heavens, the work of thy fingers, 
the moon and the stars, which thou hast ordained; what is 
man, that thou art mindful of him?" wrote the ancient 
Hebrew Psalmist many centuries ago. And his answer re- 
vealed a high opinion of the dignity of man. Thou hast 
made him but little lower than God, and crowned him with 
glory and honor. Thou makest hi to have dominion over 
the works of thy hands; thou hast put all things under his 
feet" 

This is one attitude toward the problem of man's place 
in the universe. It is the belief that man is the crowning 
creation of the entire creative process, and that he may 



54 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

rule over everything in the universe. Man is "but little 
lower than God." 

Another belief about man's place in nature is expressed 
by the Biblical author o "Ecclesiastes." This skeptical in- 
dividual teaches, **For that which befaHeth the sons o 
men befalleth beasts ... as tihe one dieth, so dieth the 
other . . . man hath no pre-eminence above tie beasts. 
... AH go unto one place, all are of the dust, and all re- 
turn to dust." 

Here is extreme pessimism about man. He is nothing but 
dust, a miserable worm with no pre-eminence or power. 
He suffers, struggles, is beaten down by the forces of the 
universe which are mighty and powerful* His life is a "way 
of suffering," a "vale of tears and sorrows/* 

As the early wise men of Judaism thought about tfng 
problem, so thought those of other races and peoples. The 
Egyptians, Babylonians, Assyrians, Phoenicians, and other 
early peoples strove to understand man in relation to his 
universe. And there were among them optimists who 
placed man above all else in the universe, and pessimists 
who saw him as nothing more than an insignificant sec- 
ond in time. 

Marts Importance According to the 
Early Greek Philosophers 

While tie very early Greeks did not deal directly with 
the problem of man's place in the universe, their theories 
of the nature of the universe left man, by implication, as a 
part of this universe. For THALES, for example, man, as 
everything else in the universe, was made of water. Man, 
like all else in nature, came to be by a natural process and 
in due time returns to the original stuff of tie universe. 

In the thinking of all these early Greeks, nature is su- 
preme, and man is a part of nature. HERACUTOS taught 
that man is part of the universal fire, he is subject to the 
law of the universe. He wrote, This one order of things 
neither any one of the gods nor of men has made, but it 
always was, is, and ever shall be, an ever-living fire, 
kindling according to fixed measure and extinguished ao- 



MAN'S PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 55 

cording to fixed measure." Here is a definite idea of the ab- 
solute supremacy of the universe, of nature. Man, as every- 
thing else including the gods, is subject to this universe and 
can do nothing to change it or to escape. 

According to EMPEDOCLES, man, like all other things in 
the universe, is composed of the elements of the universe: 
earth, air, fire, and water. All things in the universe are 
alive and have the power of thought Man differs from all 
else in that he has more of this power. 

The Atomiste taught that man was the result of a min- 
gling of atoms just as was a tree, a star, or anything else. 
The human individual has an abundance of "soul atoms" 
which he breathes in and out throughout life. When this 
process ceases, he dies and the soul atoms are scattered. 

All the Greek thinkers before the time of the Sophists 
thought of man as a part of the universe, composed of the 
same elements as everything else in the universe, and sub- 
ject to the same laws of the universe. In man some of the 
elements were a little more refined than those in other 
bodies, but that was all the difference. Man, for them, was 
a product of the universe, and had to meet the require- 
ments of the universe or be destroyed. 

The Sophists took the opposite position as regards man. 
They thought of man as the center of the universe. "Man," 
said PROTAGORAS, the most noted of the Sophists, "is the 
measure of all things." Protagoras, along with the other 
Sophists, turned from the study of nature to the study of 
man and his relationships. For them, man was no longer 
tied to the universe and subject to its inevitable laws. 
Rather, he was thought of as free, as able to determine his 
own fate, to mould the universe, or at least that part which 
was of most importance to him, in such a way that his de- 
sires would be satisfied. The Sophists tore man loose from 
natural law and attempted to make him the master of his 
fate. 

Thus the Sophists opened up the problem of man's place 
in nature. They became skeptical of man's power to under- 
stand this universe and concentrated upon a study of man 
himself and man's relationship to other men. 



56 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

The Positions of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 

SOCRATES agreed with the Sophists in turning his 
thoughts away from problems of the universe. "He set his 
face against all discussions of such high matters as the na- 
ture of the universe; how the 'cosmos/ as the savants phrase 
it, came into being; or by what forces tie celestial phe- 
nomena arise. To trouble one's brain about such matters 
was, he argued, to play the fool.* His interest was in man 
and man's problems. To know what is rigiht and to live by 
the right is more important than to know how the universe 
came into being. Man, for Socrates, is the center, the pivot, 
of all that is worth thinking about. 

PLATO felt that the Sophists had gone to the extreme in 
making man the center of the universe. He saw value in 
this point of view, but he realized that it was not com- 
plete. He also recognized that the tibinkers of early Greece 
had something to contribute. Therefore, he attempted to 
find a solution to the problem of man's place in the uni- 
verse which would satisfy the best in the thought of both 
the early Greeks and the Sophists. 

Man, Plato taught, is truly the measure of all things, be- 
cause there lie in him certain universal principles, notions, 
concepts, or ideas which are basic to all knowing. These 
ideas correspond to reality, the real world. Man, in his 
thinking, is able to grasp tie true nature of things. 

The true universe, as we have seen in the previous chap- 
ter, is, for Plato, a universe of changeless, pure, eternal 
ideas. Man can rise to a state in which he can contem- 
plate, can know these ideas. Man can know the "univer- 
sals." 

Further, man is, Plato believed, a creation of the uni- 
verse. Pure idea is impressed upon matter and the universe 
which we experience is created. We experience other in- 
dividuals. We also experience ourselves, our bodies. All 
these have come into being as ideas have been impressed 
upon matter. But man is the only creation which can come 
to know these ideas and to understand the process by 



MAN'S PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 57 

which things of nature came into being. In this way Plato 
emphasizes the unique place of man in the universe. Man 
is not like the animals, although his creation took place in 
somewhat the same way as theirs. His *souT is part of the 
divine reason which has entered the body and which is 
capable of knowing the eternally real things of the universe. 

When this rational part of man comes into the body, it 
is hindered, held down, clouded by the body which is mat- 
ter. Its task is to overcome this disadvantage and rise above 
the body. The Philosopher, as Plato sees him, does rise 
above the body and dwells in a realm of mind in which he 
can know that which is real, ideas. 

For ARISTOTLE, likewise, man is a creation in the same 
way as are all other objects in the universe. In fa' we find 
matter and form. But man is to be distinguished from all 
other objects in nature by the fact that he possesses reason. 
Like all lower forms of life, plants for example, man has 
vital functions. Also, like all animals, he has the power to 
imagine, remember, to experience desire, pain, pleasure, 
and the like. But unlike either plants or animals, man has 
the power to think. His reason is creative. This is the spark 
of the divine in man. 

Thus, although the Sophists and both Pkto and Aristotle 
were primarily interested in man, each had to think of man 
as living in an environment. The Sophists concentrated 
upon man's, social environment and the problems involved. 
Plato and Aristotle saw man not only as a member of this 
environment, but also as an individual in a universe. In the 
case of both philosophers, man is thought of as the highest 
creation, a being who in some way partakes of that which 
is divine in the universe. Although man is of nature, a crea- 
ture in which is to be found matter, he is also of the divine, 
able to approach the divine because he is of the same na- 
ture as the divine. Man has within him that which rises 
above matter and approaches that which is most ideal in 
the universe. Thus, man is not lost in the jumble of sense- 
less matter, but can overcome matter and reach out to- 
ward the divine. 



58 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

The Views of the Later Greek Thinkers 

To the Stoic, man is a part of the universal order. In- 
deed, in man is to be found the entire universe in minia- 
ture. His nature is the same as that of the All. Thus, in man 
as in the universe, reason should rule and he should subor- 
dinate himself to the law of the universe. Each man has a 
prescribed place in the divine order. He should discover 
this place and fit himself into it. Thus, man should live ac- 
cording to nature, as the divine reason directs. 

It is evident that the Stoic philosophy subordinates man 
to that which is the universal ideal. Being a unit in the 
whole and subject to its demands, man is happy when he 
understands these demands and obeys them gladly. 

Man's Importance According to the 
Early Christian Thinkers 

Although all these Greek philosophers recognized the 
fact that man is both matter and spirit, they emphasized 
the spirit, and were optimistic in the belief that man could 
overcome the disadvantages of matter. Christianity had no 
such optimism. For it, matter loomed large and foreboding 
and life was a constant struggle to escape its implications. 
Indeed, for Christianity, God, or the divine, was so pure 
and matter so far from God that pessimism was the only 
possible outcome. 

Matter, for the Christian thinkers, was the principle of 
evil. So long as man was in part matter he was evil and 
needed redemption. When the soul became attached to 
matter, it fell from divine grace, and the only way back 
was through some special act of the divine which would 
negate matter and release man from its clutches. 

The Apologists taught that the whole world was made 
by God for man, to serve as an arena in which man might 
win eternal salvation. Further, man was given a dominant 
place in the universe. He was the ruler of all He was put 
in the world to tend and govern it. 

But some men chose to disobey God, and fell into sin. 
They turned from God to matter. Through divine grace 



PLACE IN THE TO4TVEKSE 59 

they may regain their lost divinity and live eternally with 
God, 

The creative principle of the universe, God, made man 
his masterpiece, but made it possible for this masterpiece 
to destroy itself. Nevertheless, God is thought of as desir- 
ing and striving for man's redemption and as having made 
this possible through Jesus Christ. 

This point of view was developed by SAINT AXJGUSTINE. 
For him God is the cause of everything, the universe and 
man. But man is God's highest creation, a union of body 
and soul. Man's life on earth is a pilgrimage to God. In- 
deed, in comparison to what awaits man after death, this 
life is actually not life but death. Here is the typical Chris- 
tian contempt for the world and hope for another world 
beyond the grave. 

Augustine believed that the first man, Adam, set the pat- 
tern for all future life of men. Adam, he taught, com- 
mitted sin and thus handed on to all men the effects of this 
sin. He corrupted the entire human race, so that all men are 
condemned to sin for all times. Adam's sin, therefore, is 
hereditary. But God can reform corrupted man by his 
grace. And God has chosen certain men for salvation and 
certain others for eternal punishment. This is the doctrine 
known as "predestination." 

Thus man, a creation of the all-ruling power of the uni- 
verse, created out of nothing, inherits the weaknesses and 
sins of the first man. He must pay the price for this sin. 
But the all-ruling power can and does select some men for 
forgiveness and leaves others to the natural results of 
Adam's sin. Man is lost forever unless the Creator of the 
universe chooses to save him. 

The Views of the Medieval Christian Thinkers 
This general idea was carried over into the period of 
Christian thought known as Scholasticism, from the ninth 
to the thirteenth centuries. The first of the great Scholastics, 
or philosophers of this period, was JOHN Scorus ERIGENA. 
He taught that man is a revelation of the divine principle 
which created the entire universe and is that universe. But 



6O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

man is also a living spirit responsible for his fall away 
from God. He is a creation of God, but is able to draw 
away from God, to sin. 

This attempt to exalt God as the creator of the universe 
and yet give to man some dignity reached its fullness in the 
great dispute regarding the relationship between "univer- 
sals" and individuals. If the universals are all supreme, 
then the individual man can count for little in the universe. 
He is but a mere incident, unimportant The really impor- 
tant things are these universals. Mankind is important, the 
particular man is not. God is the most important, and all 
else is secondary. Thus, philosophers began to ask, What 
part does the individual play in things? Is he a mere pup- 
pet on wires pulled here and there by a divine creator? Or 
do his actions, his desires, his struggles actually mean 
something in the scheme of things? 

WILLIAM OF CHAMPEAUX taugjit that the universal is 
completely present in every individual so that each in- 
dividual differs from another only in accidental properties. 

PETER ABELABD held that universals cannot be entities 
apart from things but are in some way in things. God is in 
his creatures. 

This reasoning led, on the part of some philosophers of 
this period, to a definite pantheism. They argued that uni- 
versals are real and that God is the highest universal. Thus 
he is the most real thing in the universe and all else is an 
expression of his divine essence. Man, then, is God, and 
will eventually return to the totality, the whole, from which 
he has come. 

This Scholastic movement, with its problems and difficul- 
ties, reaches its climax in THOMAS AQTJINAS. This thinker set 
himself the task of showing that the universe as a revelation 
of God is rational He taught that the universals exist in 
particular objects as the essence of things. But matter is the 
material in which these universals are implanted. Man, 
then, is the universal "mankind" and matter. 

God created the universe, including man, out of nothing, 
according to Aquinas. Man is both matter and spirit, one 



PLACE IN" THE UNIVERSE 6l 

person in which are to be found two principles, mind and 
body. He is dragged down by matter, the body, and must 
seek redemption from his inherited sin. 

Throughout this period of human thinking, the so-called 
Middle Ages, man is thought of as a creation of the divine, 
and, in some way, a being in which is a spark of the divine. 
But man is also of the earth. He is material, and through 
this material part he inherits the sin of the first man, Adam. 
Thus man is debased and must' seek salvation from the 
Creator. The universe is both matter and spirit. Man par- 
takes of both. Therefore part of the universe is thought of 
as pulling man upward toward the divine and another part 
is pulling him down. 

This fact led to the doctrine of "contempt for the world," 
At the extreme was the belief that everything in this world 
was evil and that man should attempt to escape from it. 
Life was thought of as a pilgrimage, a testing period, a time 
of trial and tribulation. Either by good deeds, prayer and 
fasting, or by the grace of God man might escape the conse- 
quences of his material part and come eventually into the 
realm of pure spirit 

Thus, for many thinkers of the period there were actu- 
ally two universes, one of matter and the other of the spirit 
The material universe was the cause of man's sin, and actu- 
ally sought his eternal destruction. It was his enemy. But 
the spiritual universe sought his salvation and eternal bless- 
edness. This Was the abode of all that is good, the home of 
the divine. 

In their attempt to conserve the spiritual values of the 
universe, Christian philosophers leaned heavily in the direc- 
tion of complete contempt for the physical, material uni- 
verse. However, some of these men were not willing to go 
to this extreme. They saw that such a solution would actu- 
ally be no solution at all. It was dimly apparent to them 
that some way had to be found to reconcile the physical 
and the spiritual in man and in the universe. 

During the Middle Ages the Christian Church was the 
dominant factor in human thinking and living. Its doctrine 
of man's relationship to the Creator and ruling power of 



62 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHTT.OSOPHEBS 

the universe was supreme. Whatever philosophers thought, 
it was not allowed that they seriously question the doctrine 
that the Creator was supreme, and that man, one of his 
creation, was subordinate to his laws and will. 

But the thinking mind of man would not rest contented 
with this situation. There were many philosophers who 
rebelled against the complete dominance of the Church. 
Although they did not state directly that man's dignity 
could not he maintained under such restrictions, their think- 
ing gradually led them to emphasize the power of the hu- 
man. The whole trend of thought known as Nominalism 
stressed the belief that man, the individual, was of most 
importance, and general ideas, universals, reals, were mere 
ideas in man's mind. WILLIAM OF OCCAM, for example, 
taught that universals exist only as ideas or thoughts in the 
human mind and have no other reality. 

As Seen by the Forerunners of the Renaissance 

This growing stress upon man and his power and dignity 
was symbolic of a trend in human thought. It was the stir- 
ling of a giant who had been asleep and during his sleep 
had been tied and fettered until he could no longer move, 
Slowly the giant broke his bonds, stood up, and proclaimed 
his power to the world. Man dared to assert his ability to 
control the world, to know its innermost secrets and, by the 
power of his intellect, to master its ways and turn them to 
his desires. Of such was the Renaissance of the human 
spirit. It was an emphasis upon the human in the universe, 
and, therefore, has been called "Humanism/* 

In the philosophies of Luixmco VIVES, PETRXJS RAMUS, 
PABACELSUS, and BERNARDINO TELESIO this belief in man's 
power to force the universe to his desiring is evident. These 
men were among the pioneers of this rebellion against the 
forces which would crush man down, subordinate him to 
the universe. Although their ideas were crude, magical, 
and full of superstitions in which we cannot believe today, 
they were seeking to free man and place in his hands the 
tools for his mastery of the universe. What modern scien- 
tists have done for us, these men attempted to do for their 



PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 63 

age. They attempted to study and control nature with the 
knowledge and understanding which they possessed, and 
as such were forerunners of modern, science* 

As more and more investigations were made into the 
nature of the universe, this understanding and control grew. 
Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, and Newton studied the uni- 
verse and told their fellows how it worked. Of course the 
Church saw what was happening, and strove earnestly to 
root out these new forces. But the spirit of man had caught 
a faint glimpse of the future and would not be denied en- 
trance into this promised land. Never again would man be 
satisfied to bow in utter subjection to the powers of the uni- 
verse. He would stand erect and demand the right to chal- 
lenge the universe and master its secrets. This was indeed a 
new day for man and the birth of a new conception of man's 
place in the universe. 

The Positions of Bacon and Hobbes 

The opening guns of this new period, the period of mod- 
ern philosophic thought, were fired by those philosophers 
who emphasized the necessity for a careful and accurate 
study of the universe. FRANCIS BACON "gave conscious ex- 
pression to this new scientific spirit.* He would have man 
dear his mind of all the old and untrue ideas of the past 
and study the universe in an unprejudiced manner. As man 
observes and brings the fruits of his observations together, 
he will discover likenesses and differences among events 
and objects of the universe. In this way he will establish 
laws or consistencies among happenings upon which he can 
depend in all subsequent action. 

Bacon laid great stress upon the value of accurate un- 
derstanding of the universe, but he was unwilling to aban- 
don completely the religious ideas of the past. He recog- 
nized, as it was inevitable that he should, that sometimes 
religious ideas and the discoveries of careful observation 
were contradictory. But he argued that man must believe 
both. "As we are obliged to obey the divine law, though our 
wills murmur against it, so we are obliged to believe in the 
word of God, though our reason is shocked by it" 



64 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Bacon was on the fence. He saw the necessity of study- 
ing the universe and mastering its secrets. But he could not 
go over completely to this as a source of knowledge. It was 
he, however, who laid the groundwork for man's gradual 
swing to science and away from religion. 

THOMAS HOBBES was not troubled about this division. 
He went over completely to the scientific position and de- 
veloped a purely materialistic philosophy. Everything in 
the universe, including man, is, for Hobbes, material in mo- 
tion. Thus man's task is to understand the laws of motion 
and thereby to understand the universe. Having gained this 
understanding of the immutable and eternal laws of nature, 
man can adjust them to his will. 

The Views of Descartes and Spinoza 

REN DESCARTES held that everything in nature must be 
explained mechanically and that anything spiritual must 
be reconciled with this. His theory began with one absolute 
substance, God, and two relative substances, mind and mat- 
ter. In man we find both mind and matter. Although 
these two are united in imn, they do not influence each 
other. The body operates by purely mechanical laws while 
mind is spiritual. 

Man, then, partakes of the two relative substances of 
which all else in the universe is made. Man is of the uni- 
verse, for Descartes. As part of nature, he is mechanical 
to the extreme, he is a machine which operates by natural 
laws just as a watch might operate. Mind is distinct from 
body and is thus eliminated from nature. But man is com- 
posed of both. 

For SPINOZA, everything in the universe is actually sub- 
stance or God. The two attributes of God, extension and 
thought, are found in man. Man is a form of God or the 
universal substance or reality. Each individual man is a 
mode of extension, or body, and a mode of thought. In- 
deed, everything in the universe is both a mode of matter 
and a mode of mind. But, while in all objects save man 
these two modes are fairly simple, in man they are com- 



PLACE IN THE TOUVERSE 65 

plex, composed of many parts. Further, in man, mind is 
conscious of its own actions, is self-conscious. 

But there is no relation between man's mind and his 
body. Neither can influence the other. Nevertheless both 
mind and body are so constructed that what happens in 
one is accompanied by a similar happening in the other. 
Thus we seem to be affected by what happens in the 
body. 

For Spinoza, then, aH the universe is God or substance 
in the form of both mind and body. Man is a unit in this 
whole. He is both mind and body, 

Man's Place as Seen ly Locke, 'Berkeley, and Hume 

A somewhat different conception of man's place in the 
universe is held by JOHN LOCKE. For him man is a part of 
the world, but a part which is sensitive to the world round 
about Being sensitive, man has ideas about the world 
which come through the sense organs, through experience, 
Although man is both mind and body, the mental part is 
influenced by the body and the body by the mental. There 
is, then, interaction between the two parts which make up 
man. 

For Locke, besides these two substances of mind and 
body, there is another spiritual substance, God, God has 
made the universe out of nothing and has arranged it so 
that it acts as we find it acting through our experiences. 

With Locke, man's reason is established as the ultimate 
test of everything in the universe, Locke agrees that an 
outer world exists and that God exists and has created the 
world. But he attempts to prove all this in such a way 
that it will be reasonable, that it will satisfy man's mind. 
Human reason, for him, becomes the final test of revela- 
tion. Locke's followers sought to carry this line of reason- 
ing further and seek the true revelations of God in the laws 
of nature. With them, Christianity becomes a rational re- 
ligion and loses its mystery. 

Thus, the individual man is coming into his own. He is 
to be the judge of the universe. His reason is the court of 



66 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

last appeal. He must understand before he accepts a thing 
as true. 

GEORGE BERKELEY carries this idea further by eliminat- 
ing the material universe and making man the seat of 
everything in the universe. For him there is no universe 
outside of mind, either the human mind or the mind of 
God. Existence is that which is perceived, and nothing ex- 
ists when there is no mind to perceive it. Bodies, the uni- 
verse, have no existence outside of mind. Thus the theory 
of a substance outside of mind which causes the ideas in 
mind must be given up as wholly meaningless. Our sensa- 
tions come to us not from material objects but from the 
mind of God. 

The complete, logical outcome of this position is devel- 
oped by DAVID HUME. He makes man, and man alone, the 
center and whole of the universe. Since all that we can 
know, he argues, is our own ideas, there can be no material 
or spiritual substance causing them. The universe, all the 
universe tibat we can prove, is our ideas in succession. These 
ideas arise from unknown causes, and we are not correct 
in supposing them to be caused. We may believe in a cause 
of our ideas, or we may believe in the existence of God and 
a world outside of us, but we cannot prove either by any 
rational method known to man. 

Hume had led men to the point where he must distrust 
himself. That fervent enthusiasm for mastery of the uni- 
verse here had cold water thrown upon it. Man had at- 
tempted to understand the universe and thereby control 
it. Philosophers had abandoned gradually the idea of rev- 
elation and set up the human mind as the source of all 
knowledge. They seemed to be making remarkable head- 
way when Locke brought them up quick with his insist- 
ence that they stop to examine the powers of the human 
mind. Berkeley and Hume began where Locke left off and 
carried the examination further, to what they believed to 
be the logical conclusion of the position taken. Hume left 
man standing alone, his universe within his mind, and un- 
able to prove by the method long cherished that there was 
a universe, a cause of his ideas, or even that he himself 



PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 6/ 

existed. Does man stand alone, isolated? Is it necessary that 
we think of a mere succession of ideas traveling through 
space as the end-all? This was the problem which Hume 
left to those thinkers who followed hfay 

The Views of Leibnitz 

While this advance toward isolation was progressing in 
England, a somewhat different movement was evident in 
Germany. It stemmed from the work of Spinoza and was 
developed by the German thinker GOTTFRIED WJT.HET,M 
LEIBNITZ. It will be remembered that Spinoza had thought 
of everything in the universe, including man, as both ma- 
terial and spiritual, and that these were attributes of the 
one substance, God. Leibnitz broke substance up into an 
infinite number of small bits or monads. His world was 
built out of these self-contained units, these building blocks 
of the universe. 

Man, for Leibnitz, was a construct of monads, but dif- 
fered from the inorganic in that he had a central, control- 
ling monad or souL God had so arranged the universe that 
every monad acted in harmony with every other monad. 
Thus, though God was there in the beginning to start the 
universe going, he was in no way a part of the universe after 
the start. He could withdraw and let the monads unite 
and separate according to their nature. Thus, Leibnitz's 
universe is wholly mechanical Man, and all nature, is sub- 
ject to law, order, uniformity. 

Here is a mechanical universe driven onward to creation 
and dissolution by inexorable laws which are of the nature 
of the universe. Man, as part of this process, is driven 
along with all the rest of die universe. Although man is, 
in some way, the goal of the divine creative will and is, 
therefore, contained in the universe from the beginning, he 
is part of the natural whole and subject to its pre-estab- 
lished laws. 

Although this point of view differed in many respects 
from that of Locke and his successors, both streams of 
thought led in the direction of a mechanical interpretation 
of the universe and of man within it. Descartes had moved 



68 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

in this direction. Man, to Mm, was a machine. Leibnitz re^ 
duced matter to force. Thus, a mechanistic world view 
gradually became popular throughout the philosophic 
world. As a result, the dominant point of view in many 
quarters was to the effect that all nature was governed by 
kw and that everything in the universe was a product of 
nature. This led, naturally, to great interest in the sciences 
and intense study of them. Science seemed to offer great 
hope for man. 

The Position of Rousseau 

It was JEAN JACQUES ROTOSEATJ who shocked the philo- 
sophic world and shook its faith in this process. For Rous- 
seau, man was not a machine, part of the mechanical uni- 
verse. Rather, he was a thing of feeling, sentiment. Science, 
culture, Rousseau taught, had bound man in chains which 
were destroying all that was really human* Rousseau pro- 
posed to cast off this shell of civilization and free man for 
the full development of all his capacities. Indeed, Rousseau 
believed that science had isolated man from nature and 
that man's salvation lay in an escape from the bonds of 
science and a return to nature. 

Kant; 8 View of Man's Importance 

This bold challenging of the trend of the age, this plea 
for a return to nature in all its richness and fullness, in- 
fluenced perhaps the greatest of all modern philosophers, 
IMMANTJEL KANT. 

Kant undertook the task of restoring man to his dominant 
place in the universe. This necessitated the answering of 
questions raised by the philosophers who had preceded 
him. It was his task to limit Hume's skepticism on the one 
hand, and the old dogmatism on the other, and to refute 
and destroy materialism, fatalism, atheism, as well as senti- 
mentalism and superstition." It was no small undertaking, 
and one that waited for the coming of a mind of the great- 
ness of Kant's. 

Man, Kant taught, is part of the universe of objects and 



PLACE IN THE TJNIVEBSE 69 

things. But actually, although he can be certain of the ex- 
istence of this world apart from himself, he cannot know it. 
All that he can know is that world which his mind, because 
of its nature, constructs from the sensations received by 
contact with this outer universe. Here he is in agreement 
with the essential positions of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. 
Knowledge is confined to ideas. 

But this is not alL Man is able to reason and, on the basis 
of this, he can form ideas of the outer world, of God, free- 
dom, and immortality* Thus man, by virtue of reason, can 
act as though there is an outer world, as though this world 
and himself were created by a Creator, as though he is free 
and possessor of a soul which cannot perish. 

Thus, while Kant acknowledges that from the point of 
view of knowledge, man is caught in the clutches of his 
own ideas, this is only part of the picture. The other side 
is that there are factors within man which justify his as- 
suming the existence of all for which Rousseau was fight- 
ing and more. Herein the dignity of man in the universe is 
restored. Kant believed that he had solved the problems 
left by his predecessors and that he had solved them well. 
He believed that man could again stand up and face the 
universe, confident in his power to understand it and con- 
trol it to his destiny. He was certain that he had restored to 
man the dignity which the skepticism of Hume had virtu- 
ally destroyed. 

Kant gave to the philosophic world the due to all that 
seemed of value to men. He had suggested with strong and 
appealing arguments that there is a higher kind of truth 
than that offered by human intelligence, the moral law 
within us which guarantees the world of values. This clue 
fascinated Kant's immediate followers. Consequently, they 
set about to develop it to the fullest and, by so doing, to 
give man assurance of his power and dignity in the uni- 
verse. 

Fichte, ScheUing, Schletermacher, and Hegel 

JOHANN GOTTLIEB FICHTE made the principle of freedom 
central to his whole philospphy. Man, for him, is funda- 



70 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

mentally a free agent, not a mere link in a predetexmined 
cham of material events. Self-determining activity is the 
supreme characteristic of man* Fichte sought to prove this 
thesis by a method similar to that of Kant* He argued that, 
although theoretical reason cannot prove the primacy of 
freedom, we must accept such a principle as ultimate be- 
cause only by so doing can we satisfy the demands of our 
moral nature, give to life value and meaning. 

Further, the fundamental principle of the universe for 
Fichte is a universal, free, self-deterinining activity. This 
he called the Absolute ego. It is a reality above all in- 
dividual beings, a universal active reason which is, like- 
wise, in every individual. Man, then, is part of the uni- 
versal ego. He partakes of the nature of the universe. He is 
dominated by this universal life process. 

This ego, this universal activity, expresses itself in man 
and in nature. The tree, the table, the beast, and man are 
ell expressions of this fundamental principle. Man is the 
highest expression of the creative ego which is the universe. 

In making this free, creative principle, this spirit or mind, 
the fundamental factor of the universe, and in thereby de- 
livering man from the deadly mechanism into the clutches 
of which earlier philosophers had tended to condemn him, 
both Kant and Fichte were answering a deep-seated desire 
of mankind to find in the nature of the universe Justification! 
for its deepest yearnings and highest hopes* FRJEDBICH 
WTT.HET.M JOSEPH SCHELUNG was fascinated by the possi- 
bilities of this theory. Being of a poetic and artistic temper^ 
ament, he carried Fichte's conception further and taught 
that the universe was a work of art created by the great 
artist of the universe. The universe, including man, is, for 
Schelling, a living, evolving system, an organism in which 
each part has its place, just as each color of a work of art 
fits into the whole to make a masterpiece. 

Naturally this point of view fitted into the thought and 
temperament of the poets, artists, and creative geniuses of 
the period. Lessing, Herder, and Goethe, only to mention a 
few, felt that here was philosophic expression of that which 
was deepest in their natures. Here was the artist's universe, 



MAN^S PLACE IN THE UGNIVEBSE 71 

and in it was a place where the artist would feel at home 
and contented. 

FRIEDRICH EBNST DANIEL SCHLEIEHMACHER identified 
God with the universal creative principle of the universe, 
the source of all life. God is in the world, but is more than 
the world. Men, individual egos, are self -determining prin- 
ciples, each with his own specific talent and nook in the 
scheme of things. Each individual is necessary to the 
whole. If the universe is to realize itself to the fullest, is to 
create to the limit of its ability, each unit, each ego, must 
create to its limit. Man is necessary to the complete self- 
realization of the universe. 

The whole Idealistic movement in philosophy, of which 
both Fichte and Schelling are representatives, interpreted 
the universe from the point of view of man. GEORG Wn> 
HELM FRIEDBICH HEGEL employed the same method. A 
study of man reveals certain facts and factors. As man, so 
the universe of which man is a part. So reasoned the 
Idealists. 

In man, Hegel found certain logical processes operating. 
He recognized that the human mind naturally moves from 
the statement of a fact to a statement of its opposite. For 
example, war is evil. But, it is evident that good can and 
has come of war. Thus, war must also be good. Having 
recognized both these contradictory facts, the human mind 
moves on to discover some basis for reconciling them. Hegel 
believed that this was the way in which all thinking takes 
place. First, we propose a thesis: war is evil Then, we pro- 
pose the antithesis: war is good. The final proposition is the 
synthesis: despite the evils that come from war, there are 
certain values which men realize in war. 

As with the human mind, so with the universal mind, 
reasoned HegeL The universe is like man and the processes 
in the universe are the same processes, on a larger scale of 
course, which we find in the mind of man. Reality is, for 
Hegel, a logical process of evolution. It, too, has its thesis, 
antithesis, and eventual synthesis. Man is the pattern of 
which the universe is the complete realization. Man is the 
universe in miniature. Man is a microcosm of the great 



72 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GKEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

macrocosm; that is, man is a little universe which is a 
miniature of the whole universe. 

For Hegel, then, it makes no difference where we begin 
in our studies, the result will be the same. If we begin with 
man and move out to nature, we find like processes at 
work. If we study the universe first, and move to man, we 
shall find an equal similarity. 

In the approach of the Idealists we recognize the hand of 
the Sophists, Socrates, and Plato at least* The interest of 
these Greek thinkers, as we have seen, was primarily in 
man. They were not interested in the universe except as it 
affected man and his relations with his fellows. They began 
with a study of man. But inevitably they arrived at a theory 
of the universe. However, in each case, the universe was 
interpreted in terms of man. Take Plato, for example. He 
found that the highest in man was idea. He saw man at- 
tempting to mould the world to fit bis ideas just as the 
artist moulds day to give concreteness to an idea. From 
this he reasoned that the supreme thing in the universe was 
idea, pure and untouched by matter. But, as man used 
ideas to mould matter, so the divine creative principle of 
the universe used ideas to mould the universe. 

So, down the ages has come this approach to the uni- 
verse, the approach through man and his nature. As man, 
so the universe, they reasoned. 

The Views of Later German Thinkers 

But there has been another, likewise powerful, tradition 
in philosophy. The leaders of this tradition, as we have 
seen, study first the universe, the material universe. Having 
discovered its laws and nature, they place man in the chain 
of inevitable causes and effects. If the universe is a machine 
governed by unchangeable laws, so is man a machine. 

JOHANN FRIEDRICH HERBART is representative of this lat- 
ter approach, as indicated in our first chapter. Both nature 
and man, he taught, are constituted by the coining and go- 
ing, the mingling and separating of units which he called 
"reals." The universe of reals is absolute. In it there is no 
change, growth, decay. The only change lies in our own 



MAN'S PI-ACE IN THE UNIVERSE 73 

habit of relating reals in such a way as to form objects or 
patterns. 

You have undoubtedly seen drawings which, if looked 
at steadily for a while, seem to change before your very 
eyes. Actually we know that the drawing does not change, 
but our eyes relate parts of it in different ways so that the 
picture seems to change. So, Herbart thought, must we 
think of the universe and our experiencing of it It never 
changes, but we relate the various reals in such diverse 
ways that the universe seems to change. 

Man, likewise, is a result of the organization of reals. 
His mental life is a fusion, organization of ideas which re- 
sult from the interaction of reals. And, Herbart believed, all 
this can be stated in purely mechanical terms. For him, 
psychology was nothing other than the mechanics of the 
mind. As Herbart saw the universe operating in terms of 
dependable laws, he reasoned that man, in all his actions, 
can be explained in the same terms. Everything in mind 
follows fixed kws. Man is part of the natural universe, is 
governed by the same kws, and can be understood and 
controlled if we know the laws. 

ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER thought in the Idealistic tradi- 
tion. He interpreted the world, the universe, in terms of the 
human individual. In man he found the will supreme. Man 
wishes, wills to do, make, or have something. This will 
drives him into action and may result in a changed en- 
vironment As with man, so the universe. Will is the funda- 
mental principle of the creative universe. All nature is an 
expression of will. In the stone, wifl is blind; in man, it is 
conscious of itself. 

Man, then, is a pattern of the universe, a pattern in 
miniature. Man is the universe greatly reduced. 

RUDOLF HERMANN LOTZE is in this same tradition. The 
universe, for him, must be understood in terms of the hu- 
man mind since the mind is the only true reality we can 
know. Mental life is present throughout nature, even to 
rocks and dirt. The human mind is the highest stage, that 
upon which mind becomes self-conscious. Man is the truest 



74 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

representation of the universe, the highest creation of the 
great creative mind which is the universe. 

Man as the model of the universe is exploited by FRIED- 
RICH NIETZSCHE. In man he finds the will to power, and be- 
lieves that this is dominant. Therefore, he reasons that this 
will to power is the fundamental factor in the universe. 
But, this universal will to power takes on, for Nietzsche, a 
sinister appearance. The universe cares nothing for man, his 
dreams and hopes. 

Since the will of man drives hfm on regardless of the 
consequences to others, so the will of the universe drives on 
despite its consequences to us. It crushes man in the storm 
and destroys hfrn in the flood. It cares not for his existence 
and knows nothing of his plans or struggles. The universe 
is not friendly to man. Life is terrible. There is no way out. 
We struggle to realize our wills only to be crashed in the 
end, to be devoured by death* 

The optimism of the Idealists has been turned against 
them by Nietzsche. They believed that the universe should 
be interpreted in terms of man if his values were to be 
preserved. Thus, as mind was the essence of man for them, 
they reasoned that the essence of the universe was mind, 
and that such a mind would be friendly to man's values. 
Nietzsche uses the same method, but finds the essence of 
man to be a will to power. When he translates this into 
universal terms, when he makes the will to power the es- 
sence of the universe, he reaches the pessimistic conclusion 
that the universe cares nothing for man and his values. 

Man's Place According to Comte 

A most radical attempt to interpret the universe in terms 
of man is to be found in the movement of philosophic en- 
deavor known as "Positivism.* The early leader of this 
movement was AUGUSTE COMTE. He took the position that 
the only source of knowledge was observation and experi- 
ence. From this we get only uniform relations between 
phenomena. As far as inner essences are concerned, we can 
know nothing. 

Consequently, we cannot know the inner essence of the 



MAN'S PLACE IN THE "UNIVERSE 75 

universe or of man. As man looks at the universe, he finds it 
operating in certain ways. This is aH he knows, and all that 
he needs to know. Thus, the universe and man's place in it 
are interpreted in terms of what man can see and experi- 
ence. 

Man finds people getting in draughts, catching cold, and 
suffering. In so far draughts are enemies of man. But he 
also finds that by regulating draughts he can keep a fire 
burning with which he can heat his house or cook his food. 
In so far draughts are friendly to rngn. All that man needs 
to know, and indeed all that he can know are these rela- 
tionships. Whether there is a basic unity behind these phe- 
nomena, man can never know and, in fact, he does not 
need to know since the fact would not change his life one 
bit. He would still stay out of certain draughts and use 
others to regulate his fire. 

Man, for Comte, is in the universe, is affected by its parts 
In various ways and is able to affect the universe in many 
other ways. As man finds regularities in the relationships 
between parts of the universe and between himself and 
these parts, he is able to foresee consequences of his actions 
and happenings among the parts, and to govern his actions, 
to a degree at least, in the light of these relationships. 

The "Positions of Mitt and Spencer 

JOHN STUART MILL contributed to this position by show- 
ing how men may discover regularities within the universe. 
His logical method of induction was a guide to assurance. 
We see many events in which there are similarities. We 
study these and discover consistencies. Experience is evi- 
dence that we can depend upon these consistencies. There- 
fore, we take the position that a certain situation will be 
followed by a certain phenomenon. We can act on this, 
Mill believed, with a high degree of assurance that we will 
not be wrong. 

As Mill found order, uniformity, inevitable sequence in 
the world which we experience, he reasoned that these 
same factors are to be found within man, since man is 
part of the universe. But, in man we find that the factors 



76 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

which must be taken into consideration are so numerous 
that it is impossible for us to predict with any bigh degree 
of certainty. Man is a very complex being. Every action of 
man is the result of a vast number of factors. Thus, al- 
though the same fundamental principles apply both in the 
universe and in man, recognition of them is easier in the 
universe since here the factors are simpler. 

For example, it is possible for an astronomer, on the 
basis of observation and experience, to predict with abso- 
lute accuracy the appearance of a comet many hundreds of 
years from now. But, to predict whether a newborn baby 
will be a doctor, lawyer, beggar, or thief, is practically im- 
possible. In the one case the factors involved are fairly 
simple, in the other they are highly complex. But, and this 
is the significant thing for our present study, Mill believed 
that, should it be possible for one to know all the factors and 
their proper weight, man would find equal certainty, uni- 
formity, and inevitableness in both cases. Indeed, in his 
treatment of social and political problems, he attempted to 
show that certain uniformities do exist and can be experi- 
enced. 

Although HERBERT SPENCER took the position that man 
can know only his experiences, he was certain that these ex- 
periences must have a cause, that there must be a universe 
outside of our experiences to cause us to experience as we 
do. Although he called this the Unknowable,'* he inter- 
preted it in terms of what he found in man. 

Since, he reasoned, man has the subjective feeling of ac- 
tivity, muscular strain, force, the Unknowable is of the 
same nature. It is activity, force. Thus the fundamental 
principle of the universe is also the fundamental principle 
of man. Man is of the universe. 

As this force is creative and active according to definite 
laws of development, so we find man a result of this crea- 
tive development. Man is a result of the evolutionary proc- 
esses which are to be found in the universe. And, further, 
as man develops, he follows these evolutionary processes. 
The law of evolution, then, is the universal law of things. 
It is the law of the development of the universe, the law 



MAN'S PI-ACE IN THE tJNIVERSE 77 

which accounts for the coming of man, and the law which 
is in man and by which he develops* 

Just as, Spencer reasoned, all things in the universe are 
results of the adaptation of the unit to the environment, so 
all that is in man is a result of a similar adaptation. Con- 
sciousness, for example, has resulted from the necessity to 
adapt to the environment Man is what he is because his 
universe, his environment, makes certain consistent and 
definite demands upon him* Thus, the law which is funda- 
mental to the universe is also fundamental to man. Man is 
part, a stage, of the on-going process which is evolution. 

The Views of James, Dewey, and Russell 

The Positivistic point of view, as developed by Comte, is 
evident in the thought of WmrjAM JAMES. He, too, places 
man at the center of the universe. For him, whatever is 
experienced is real. For him, reality is pure experience. 
Therefore, on the basis of our experience we construct a 
theory of the universe. But this theory is determined by 
what we experience. It is egocentric; that is, centered in 
man's ego. 

For James, whatever satisfies man is true; and what- 
ever does not satisfy him is false. Man finds certain con- 
sistencies in his experience. These, he reasons, are true of 
the universe. We act upon them, and the results which we 
anticipate follow. They are true. The universe, then, is the 
universe of -human experience. We interpret it in terms of 
our experience, and all the ideas we have of it result from 
our experience. 

Likewise, JOHN DEWEY thinks of man as the measure of 
the universe. The universe is that which man experiences. 
To try to go beyond this to absolute origins and finalities is 
foolishness. Man cannot get beyond his experiences. 

Reality, in the thinking of Dewey, is growing, changing, 
developing according to kws which are the laws of human 
experience. Man is part of this process. Man is in the uni- 
verse, a creation of the evolutionary process which we find 
everywhere. In him the universe comes to self-conscious- 
ness. 



78 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

As in man we find uncertainty, doubt, and a degree of 
certainty, so in the universe. Man's experience is the meas- 
ure of the universe, the only possible measure which we 
can have, for no man can get outside of his experience. 

BERTBANB RUSSELL expresses the same general position 
in his little book, A "Free Man's Worship. However, his 
conclusion, though similar in consequences to that of Nietz- 
sche, is not arrived at by the same method. Russell sees the 
universe as a great mathematical machine. It is governed 
by scientific laws which are inexorable, unchanging. Man 
is part of this system, a very small and insignificant part 

Thus, for Russell, man is caught in the enrolling of die 
great universal machine. Its laws are inevitable, and its 
nulls grind on regardless of what is thrown into the hopper. 
Man rises for a moment, thinks that he amounts to some- 
thing, but his time of exaltation is short After a brief life, 
he drops out of the scheme of things, and the universe 
moves on uncaring and unknowing. In the eternity of a 
machine universe, one individual with his values amounts 
to nothing. 

Mankind, says Russell, is like a group of shipwrecked 
sailors on a raft in a vast sea at night There is darkness all 
around. One by one they fall off the raft into the waters 
and disappear. When the last man has fallen off, the sea 
will roll on and the holes made in the water by their bodies 
will be covered over. Nature cares not for man. 

Thus, throughout the history of human thought man has 
endeavored to understand the universe as related to him- 
self. Some philosophers have arisen to tell hi that the uni- 
verse is like h and is his friend; that in the universe are 
forces which are concerned with his welfare. Indeed, the 
philosophic God is very often a being whose concern is 
for man. But there are those other philosophers who find 
the universe, and man included, a vast system of laws and 
consistencies in which human values have little or no place. 
Man lives his little day and is forgotten. 

At the extremes we have both the religious and the 
scientific positions. Religious philosophies have attempted 
fairly consistently to construct a universe that is friendly 



PLACE IN THE UNIVERSE 79 

to man and his values. They recognize the factors which 
seem to belie this position: death, sin, suffering, hopes un- 
realized. But they strive to fit these into a whole so that 
they lose their sting. God and heaven are often offered as 
the final solution of the problem. 

Scientific philosophies, on the other hand, take the uni- 
verse as they find it in the laboratory or under strict 
scientific investigation. They find only laws and inevitable 
consistencies, a great machine rolling on, a machine that 
can be depended upon to act in certain ways but which 
is unconcerned with human values. 

And there are those philosophers who try to reconcile 
both extremes. The Pragmatists are of this group, as are 
many others. But it too often happens that the mediator 
simply brings the two extremes together in an inconsistent 
mixture. 

Still the question haunts philosophy: Is the universe 
man's friend or man's enemy? 



Chapter III 
WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 

HERACLTTUS DEMOOEUTUS SOCRATES PLATO 

ARISTOTLE AQUINAS ABELARD 
HOBBES SPINOZA LOCKE LEEBNTTZ 

KANT FICHTE SCHOPENHAUER 
MILL BENTHAM SPENCER DEWEY 



What is the measure of good and evil in the world? 
How can we know whether or not an act is good or 
bad? Is there in the very nature of the universe a code 
of laws which determines good and bad? Or, is good- 
ness and badness a matter of the relation of an act to 
other acts? 



Open the book of the story of mankind anywhere and 
you will find the question being asked over and over again: 
What is good and what is evil? This has been, without 
doubt, one of the most persistent problems of philosophers 
throughout the ages. Answers have been given in abun- 
dance, answers which appeared to the particular philoso- 
pher giving the particular answer to solve the problem 
for all times, but in a very few years the problem bas arisen 
again in the thinking of others. 

Is there an absolute, ultimate, and unquestioned measure 
of good and evil, one that was established at the beginning 
of time and that will stand until time is no more? A great 
number of people have believed in such a measure, and 
there have been thinkers who have attempted to state it in 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 8l 

a code of commandments or basic principles of conduct 
for all times. The Ten Commandments of the ancient He- 
brews is an example of this trend in human thinking. Here 
is a code of conduct which is believed by many to have 
been handed down from the seat of divine authority and 
which has authority at all times and in all places. 

At the other extreme are thinkers who have believed that 
both good and evil are relative to the conditions of the 
time and place, and that an act which is good in one place 
and time will be evil in another. For example, a maniac is 
chasing a man with intent to loll him. The man passes me 
and turns to the right and disappears. Then the maniac 
comes up and asks which way his intended victim went. 
I say that he turned left, and thereby save the life of an 
innocent man. This untruth is good, they argue in an at- 
tempt to prove that truth is not always good. 

Between these two extremes are many theories of good 
and evil. Philosophers desiring to prove the absolute good- 
ness of God have difficulty at times explaining the exist- 
ence in the universe of death, suffering, and ill will. How 
can an all-good God create a world in which there are these 
apparent evils, they ask? And they have offered many in- 
genious arguments to reconcile a good God and an evil 
world. 

And so, throughout the history of man's thought we dis- 
cover the problem of good and evil (which we speak of as 
"ethics** or "the ethical problem**) persistently challenging 
each philosopher. 

Good and Evil According to the Early Greek Philosophers 

HERACLITUS, the Greek philosopher of change, believed 
that good and evil were two notes in a harmony. He found 
many things changing into their opposites. Ice, which is 
hard, changes into water, which is soft This led him to be- 
lieve that the combination of opposites resulted in a whole 
in which there is harmony. Just as in music harmony re- 
sults from the combination of low and high notes, so in the 
universe harmony results from the combination of oppo- 
sites, good and evil. 



82 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

We, he taught, see only the opposites, the good and the 
evil. But God sees the harmony, so that for him all things 
are fair and just in that they are parts of a great universal 
harmony. Thus, the good life for man is that life lived in 
harmony with the universal reason, the law which per- 
vades all things. Man should seek to understand this har- 
mony in the universe and to fit into it so that his actions 
are in accord with the principle governing the whole uni- 
verse. 

The early Greek philosophers, interested primarily as we 
have seen in the problem of the nature of the universe, 
taught that there were all-pervasive laws controlling the 
entire universe. Therefore, goodness for them was to be 
found in harmony with these laws. Further, they were so 
enchanted by this idea of law that even evil did not bother 
them much. Evil, for them, was but a phase, a note in the 
universal harmony and, thus, was not really evil but was 
another kind of good, a necessary part of the good whole. 

As philosophers turned from their interest in the universe 
to a new interest in man, they began to ask most seriously 
the question: What kind of a life is good for man to live? 
How can one so regulate his life among his fellows that it 
is good? 

DEMOCRTTUS, the leading figure of the Greek Atomists, 
taught that the goal of life is happiness. At all times man 
should seek happiness. For him, happiness was an inner 
condition or state of tranquillity which depended upon 
harmony of the soul. He taught that one should not de- 
pend for happiness upon things of the world since these 
come and go and a lack of them causes unhappiness. 
Rather, happiness should be a state of the inner man, a 
balance of life, an attitude which combines reflection and 
reason. 

Goodness, for him, was not only a matter of action, but 
depended upon man's inner desire. The good man is not 
one who does good, but one who wants to do good at all 
times. "You can tell the man who rings true from the man 
who rings false," he said, "not by his deeds alone, but 
also by his desires." Such goodness brings happiness, the 
goal of Me. 



"WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 83 

\Vitb the coming of the Sophists thinking on this problem 
of good and evil entered a period of confusion. If, as Protag- 
oras held, "Man is the measure of all things," then man is 
the measure of good and evil. And, by man, the Sophists 
meant the individual man, you, me, your neighbor. Each 
one has the right to determine for himself what is good and 
what is evil. The end of this practice is, of course, chaos. 
What I consider evil, you may consider good. The Sophists 
let the matter rest here. 

As a result, each man had his own code of good and bad. 
He defied others to prove hi-m wrong or to justify their 
condemnation of him. Many representative Sophists, such 
as EUTHYDEMUS, THRASYMACHUS, and CAULICLES, taught 
that morality was mere convention, habit. That actually 
there are no moral laws, no all-inclusive principles of right 
and wrong. These men sought to justify the principle that 
each man should live as he desired, get what he wanted by 
any means possible, and frame his own code of good and 
evil. 

The result of this position was moral anarchy, pure indi- 
vidualism, and the ultimate in selfishness. Nevertheless, a 
closer study of this position reveals a tendency which is rich 
in possibilities. The Sophists were making their appeal to 
the independent human mind. They were rebelling against 
arbitrary authority in matters of morals and were arguing 
that the human mind must think for itself and in thinking 
discover a code of rigjit and wrong. The Sophists were 
champions of the individual and his independence. True, 
they went to the extreme and lost the forest by concentra- 
ting attention upon the trees. Nevertheless, they had hold of 
a thing which is very precious to modern man, freedom 
to think and to arrive at conclusions about the good and the 
evil. The Sophists challenged moral theory to justify itself 
before the bar of human reason. 

The Ethical Views of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 

SOCRATES was stimulated by the Sophists but was un- 
willing to go all the way with them. He, too, was most in- 
terested in the problems related to living a good life. Thus a 



84 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

great deal of his teaching dealt with the meaning of right 
and wrong. 

It was Socrates' firm belief that there must be a basic 
principle of right and wrong, a measure which would apply 
far beyond the beliefs of any one individual. Thus, he asked 
time and again: What is the good? What is the highest 
good by which all else in the universe is measured? And 
his answer was that knowledge is the highest good. 

If one knows what is right, he argued, he will do it "No 
man,** he said, "is voluntarily bad." When one knows that 
a thing is good he will choose to do that thing. Therefore 
the most important endeavor of man is to discover what is 
good. Socrates spent his life trying to help men discover 
what is good. Thus, for him, a life which is always in- 
quiring and trying to discover what is good is the best kind 
of life, the only life worth living. 

PLATO took up the problem of good and evil where Soc- 
rates left it. For him, goodness is tied up with his theory of 
the nature of the universe. The world of sense, he taught, 
is unreal, fleeting, changing. This is evil. The real world of 
pure, unchanging ideas is the world of good. Man can 
know this real world only through his reason. Therefore> 
reason is the highest good for man. The end or goal of life 
is release of the soul from the body so that it can con- 
template the true world of ideas. 

But man may live a just life even though he is held 
down by the body and remains in a world of changing 
shadows of real things. This can be done, Plato believed, so 
long as the rational part of man rules his every action. Plato 
thought of man as consisting of three parts. The appetites 
are concerned with bodily functions and desires. The will, 
or spiritual part of man, is concerned with action, courage, 
bravery. And the reason is concerned with the highest and 
best in man. A man is living a good life when reason rules 
the will and the appetites, and when, as a result, he is wise, 
brave, and temperate. 

Thus, a life of reason is the highest good for man, a life 
noted for wisdom, courage, and self-control. And, Plato 
taught, this kind of life will be the happy life. Happiness 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 85 

and goodness go together. However, one should not seek 
pleasure as the end of life. Pleasure comes when one has 
attained the good life, a life in which the highest, reason, 
rules the lower, wifl and appetites. 

AHISTOTLB pointed out that every action of man has 
some end in view and that these ends seem to he an endless 
chain. One acts in order to get something, but this some- 
thing is obtained in order to get something else, and so on. 
What, he asked, is the highest good, the good for which 
all else is done? He reached an answer to this question by 
pointing out that the aim of everything in the universe 
is to realize itself to the fullest. Each thing is different from 
all others. It has certain talents, abilities. Thus, it is good 
when it has realized these talents and abilities to the full- 
est. Thus, self-realization is for Aristotle the highest good, 
the goal of all else that is done. 

Now, the distinguishing feature of man is his reason. No 
other entity in the universe possesses reason. Man alone has 
this characteristic, ability. Therefore, the highest good of 
man is the complete realization of his reason. This, Aristotle 
believed, brings happiness. Pleasure accompanies the full 
realization of man's reason; it is a natural result of such 
realization. 

But, as Plato also taught, reason is only a part of man. 
He also has feelings, desires, appetites. Therefore, a good 
life is one in which all these factors are realized in perfect 
harmony, in which reason rules and the feelings and desires 
obey. The goal of human life is a rational attitude toward 
the feelings and desires. 

What is this rational attitude? Aristotle taught that it 
consisted of the "golden mean." For example, courage is to 
be thought of as a mean between cowardice and f oolhardi- 
ness. The good man is one who lives a life according to 
this golden mean, who does not go to extremes in action 
but balances one extreme over against another. 

Thus, the good life for Aristotle is one in which man re- 
alizes to the fullest the supreme part of his nature, reason. 
Such a man will be noble, just, honest, considerate, and 
will give evidence of all the other virtues of life. And he 



88 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHDLOSOPHEES 

wise, the spiritual part of man, his mind or soul, is the seat 
of good; and his body, which is thought of as matter, is 
the seat of evil. Consequently, when the soul is incor- 
porated in the body it suffers a fall from divine perfection 
and becomes predisposed to evil. Thus, the goal of man is 
freedom from the body and all its sin, and return to God 
and perfect goodness. The position of PLOTINUS was very 
similar. Matter is the source of evil and God the source of 
good. 

The Ethical Views of the Early Christian Thinkers 

Thus a definite dualism is to be seen throughout the 
Western religious tradition, a dualism borrowed in sub- 
stance from the religions of the early East. Christianity 
accepted this dualism and made it basic to its treatment of 
the whole problem of sin and redemption. 

The Apologists taught that God had created man good, 
but he turned from God to the flesh, the body. By this, 
sin came into the world. The Christian interpretation of the 
story of Adam, the first man, is a picture in symbolic terms 
of the coining of sin, a sin which was then transmitted to 
all men as original sin. Because man is man, a descendant 
of the first man, he is harassed by evil and must seek sal- 
vation through the divine grace of God. 

SAINT AUGUSTINE found that the presence of evil in the 
universe gave him no end of trouble, God, for him, was all 
good, all perfection. And God created the universe out of 
nothing. If this be true, how could a good God, all power- 
ful, create a universe in which there was evil? How account 
for evil in a world created by an all-good God? 

To solve this problem,- Augustine taught that everything 
in the universe is good. Even that which appears to be 
evil to us is actually good in that it fits into the whole 
pattern of the universe. Shadows, dark spots, are necessary 
to the beauty of a painting. If seen by themselves, broken 
away from the whole picture, they appear bad. But when 
seen in the picture they make possible the beauty of the 
whole. 

Evil, then, is relative for Augustine, and is actually an 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 89 

absence of good just as darkness is absence of light The 
evil which we find in the universe is put there by God to 
make the whole universe good. 

Further, for Augustine, the goal o all mankind is com- 
plete union with God and escape from the world. Man 
should turn his back on the pleasures of tfn's world which 
are thin and pale, and direct his attention wholly to God 
who is perfect goodness. This union with God is to be at- 
tained through love of God as opposed to love of the world. 

The Views of the Medieval Christian Thinkers 

The position of Augustine is also held very largely by the 
philosophers of Scholasticism. Believing in an all-good God 
who created everything, they had to explain apparent evil 
as actually a part of the good whole and thus actually good. 

ABELARD added a new note when he taught that the 
Tightness or wrongness of an act does not lie in the act it- 
self but in the intention of the actor. If one steals from an- 
other, the act itself is neutral. If the thief intended it as 
something good, it was thereby good. "God," he wrote, 
"considers not what is done, but in what spirit it is done; 
and the merit or praise of the agent lies not in the deed, but 
in the intention." 

If one acts in terms of what he thinks is right, if he be- 
lieves he is doing good and seeks to do good, he may err, 
but he does not siru Goodness, morality, then becomes a 
matter of conscience. The truly sinful man is one who acts 
with a desire to do wrong. He is sinful because he shows in 
his action a deliberate contempt for God. 

The greatest of the Scholastics was THOMAS AQUINAS. In 
his theory of good and evil we find the philosophy of Aris- 
totle joined with the basic principles of Christianity. God 
made everything, including man, for a purpose, and the 
highest good of all things is the realization of this purpose. 
As one realizes the purpose for which he was created, he 
reveals God's goodness. Therefore, the highest good is the 
realization of oneself as God has ordained. 

Further, the highest form of action is the contemplation 
of God. This may be done through reason or faith, but it 



go BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHEBS 

reaches its height in what Aquinas called "intuition," a 
coining to God which can be completed only in the world 
to come, in heaven. 

Aquinas follows Augustine, also, in holding that the 
goodness or badness of a particular action depends upon 
the ft* or purpose of the actor. An act may have good 
consequences, but it is not good unless the actor intended 
it to have these consequences and knew that they would 
result. However, Aquinas does not hold with Augustine 
that an evil act may be good if the actor intended it to be 
so. Intention will not make a bad act good, but it is the 
only thing that will make a good act truly good. 

The Christian doctrine of "contempt for the world" is 
prominent in Aquinasf teaching. The best way to attain 
goodness is to abandon worldly goods and seek the life of 
God. Thus, the life of the saint in a monastery devoting 
himself entirely to service to God is ideal. 

Evil, for Aquinas, is privation, a lack of the good. All 
things, created by a good God, aim at goodness. When they 
fail, evil results. 

Hie mystic teachings of MEKTER ECKHABT emphasize 
the unity of God and the individuality of man. Since God 
is the pure unity of the world, the universe, any individu- 
ality must be a breaking away from God and therefore evil. 
Consequently, the good life is one which strives to return to 
the divine unity and become one with God. "Whoever 
would see God," he writes, "must be dead to himself and 
buried in God, in the unrevealed desert Godhead, to be- 
come again what he was before he was.* 

The good life for Eckhart, then, is not one of deeds but 
one of being. We do not attain goodness by striving to do 
good. We reach that which is perfect goodness by losing 
ourselves in the unity of God. 

Christianity, and the whole Western religious movement, 
emphasized the great gulf between God and all that is less 
than God. Goodness is created by God and is to be found 
in adjustment to God's plan or purpose. Evil is in some 
way attached to matter, the body, or the world. But God, 
being the sole Creator of the universe, would not create 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? Ql 

evil. Therefore, evil must not actually be evil, but must be 
part of the great good. Not all the Christian philosophers 
held to this explanation consistently. They were confronted 
with the fact of human degradation, actions which were 
evil in intention or in consequences, by deliberate acts on 
the part of many which caused evil. Consequently, they 
had to tie this up with the body, the sinful will of man 
which was in some way inherited from Adam, or the per- 
versity of matter. 

Christianity has never been able to solve the problem of 
evil and sin. Eastern religions were more realistic in this 
matter. They did not make their gods the creators of the 
whole universe. Rather they had at least two gods, one the 
god of goodness and the other the god of evil. In traditional 
Christianity we find these two beings functioning. God is 
thought of as the source of all good, and the Devil is the 
evil principle, But, to the question TDid God create the 
Devil?" there is no answer. A dualism of good and evil 
works well until the attempt is made to account for the 
creation of the universe; but that presents difficulties which 
have not been solved. 

Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke, and Leibnitz 

Modern philosophy wrestles with the same problem, but 
has introduced many new elements in its attempt either to 
meet the original difficulty or to put the whole matter on a 
different level. 

THOMAS HOBBES was concerned, as we have seen, with 
interpreting the entire universe on a materialistic basis. 
Motion was, for him, the fundamental factor in the universe. 
Thus, good and evil were for him matters of motion. When 
motion is successful it generates pleasure, and when it is 
unsuccessful pain results. 

That which pleases a man is good, and that which causes 
pain or discomfort is evil. Thus, good and evil are, as 
Hobbes sees it, relative to the particular man. That which 
pleases one man may not please another. Consequently, 
there can be no absolute good or evil. Both depend upon 



gZ BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PfflLOSOPHEBS 

the nature of the individual at the time, and as he changes 
good things may become evil and evil things good. 

The relation of a philosopher's general view to his at- 
titude toward the question of good and evil is well 
illustrated by DESCARTES. For him, God is perfect, and in- 
capable of causing us to err. But we do fall into error and 
suffer from our mistakes. This is explained on the theory 
that the power which God has given man to distinguish 
the true from the false is not complete. Thus, man is often 
guilty of making judgments when he does not have enough 
understanding to judge accurately. In such cases he may 
choose that which is wrong, evil, rather than the good. For 
Descartes, error lies not in God's action but in ours. We 
make up our minds and act before we have sufficient evi- 
dence. 

The theory of SPINOZA is much in the same vein. Error 
is lack of knowledge. Action without knowledge will pro- 
duce results which are not desired, and pain will follow. 

As he studied the individual, Spinoza came to the con- 
clusion that the fundamental striving of everyone is to pre- 
serve himself. This striving is good. Thus, anything which 
tends to block this striving is bad, and everything which 
helps man to reach the goal of his striving is good. 

But man's striving must be rational. Merely to strive is 
not enough; he must strive intelligently, realizing what he 
is doing and its consequences. The highest happiness of 
man lies in the perfect understanding of what he is doing, 
his striving. As we come to understand our own strivings 
we recognize that, since we are modes of God, our striving 
is in truth the striving of God, for we are God. The highest 
good of man is this complete realization. In it he sees that 
by loving himself he actually loves God, Spinoza calls this 
the "intellectual love of God." 

The basic philosophic theory of JOHN LOCKE gives rise to 
his theory of good and evil. Just as all our ideas come from 
the outside and are written on the mind as one might write 
on a blank sheet of paper, so our conceptions of what is 
good and what is evil are produced. The fact is, many peo- 
ple have the same experiences and come to the same con- 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 93 

elusions. They agree that certain things are good and others 
are bad. Further, our parents have impressed upon us ideas 
of right and wrong from the first days of our lives. Later 
we come to believe that they are innate, inborn. For Locke, 
human conscience is nothing more than these ideas which 
we have had so long that they seem to be given by some 
divine power. 

Further, Locke taught that pleasure and pain are native 
to man. Nature has made it so that we enjoy happiness and 
seek to avoid pain. Therefore, those things which bring hap- 
piness are called good, and those which bring pain are 
called evil. 

But it is not always true that the same act will bring hap- 
piness to everyone. Consequently there are laws which we 
must obey under penalty of being unhappy if we refuse to 
obey. Locke believed that three groups of laws existed. 
Divine laws are those set by God to determine duty and 
sin. If we break these laws we suffer greatly. Then, there 
are civil laws established by the group as a constituted 
civil unit. These determine crime and innocence. Disobedi- 
ence is punishable by the group making the laws. The 
third group of laws are those of opinion or reputation. 
These are by far the greatest in number and are enforced 
by the mere fact that men cherish their reputations and 
do not desire the condemnation of their companions and 
friends. 

But, we learn what is good and bad by experience, by 
the experience of pain if we do evil and pleasure if we do 
good. Thus, Locke was in the ethical tradition of Hobbes 
and others who made morality largely a matter of enlight- 
ened self-interest: that is, one is good because being good 
pays the highest dividends in individual pleasure. 

Thinkers who followed Locke sought to expand this po- 
sition so as to include others, and to make morality de- 
pendent upon the happiness of others as well as upon tie 
happiness of tie individual. RICHARD CUMBEKLAND, 
founder of the Utilitarian school of thought, argued that 
man is not wholly selfish, but is basically sympathetic. 
Thus, the welfare of the group, of society, determines the 



94 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

good and the bad. LOBD SHAFTESBURY taught that man is 
interested in the welfare of both himself and society and 
that good actions result when both of these interests are 
properly balanced. FRANCIS HXJTCHESON, of this same gen- 
eral opinion, coined the phrase **the greatest good for the 
greatest number,* and made it the criterion of a good act. 

LEIBNITZ encountered the same difficulty as did many 
of his predecessors when he came to the problem of good 
and evil. In a universe of monads, how is evil possible? 
His answer was similar to that of earlier philosophers. This 
world, he taught, is "the best possible world," but it is not 
perfect. God limited himself when he expressed himself in 
finite beings. These limits result in suffering and sin. Fur- 
ther, evil serves to make good really good. It is like the 
shadows in a picture, shadows which serve to bring the 
colors into bolder relief and greater beauty. 

Further, in the human soul, he suggested, there are cer- 
tain innate princi^es which, if followed logically, lead to 
criteria of good and bad. One of these principles is that we 
should seek pleasi^re and avoid pain. Reasoning from this 
principle, we can prove that certain acts are good and 
others are bad. 

Often men do not obey these innate principles because 
of their passions and impulses, but this does not prove that 
they do not exist, Leibnitz held. Afl that this proves is that 
such men are ignorant of the principles. 

The Ethical Philosophy of Kant 

The basic problem of KANT was to discover the meaning 
of right and wrong, good and bad. He asked, How is duty 
to be defined, and what are the implications of the defini- 
tion? In attacking the problem, Kant accepted as funda- 
mental the principle, laid down by Rousseau, that the only 
absolutely good thing in the universe is the human will 
governed by respect for the moral law or the consciousness 
of duty. A moral act is one which is done out of respect for 
the moral law rather than for selfish gain or sympathy for 
others. 

Thus, for Kant, consequences are not to be taken as de- 
termining the rightness or wrongness of an act. Whether 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 9g 

the results of an act are productive of happiness or of pain 
is not the matter of greatest concern. If the actor performs 
the act with good intentions, out of respect for the moral 
law, it is thereby good. 

This moral law, in the thinking of Kant, is inherent in 
reason itself. It is a priori, before experience, in the very 
nature of human thinking. Stated in a sentence, it reads: 
"Always act in such a way that the Tna-rfm detennining your 
conduct might wefl become a universal law; act so that 
you can will that everybody shall follow the principle of 
your action.* In every instance, Kant believed, this rule, 
this "categorical imperative, 1 ' is a sure criterion of what 
is right and what is wrong. An act which you would be 
willing that anyone or everyone should perform would be 
a good act. 

This law, if thoroughly understood, is in everyone. It 
may not be recognized in the terms stated, but anyone who 
stops to think will discover that human life is possible only 
on this moral basis. Should man attempt to act contrary 
to this principle, human association would be chaotic. 

Another law, an implication of the categorical imperative, 
is stated by Kant; "Act so as to treat humanity, whether 
in thine own person or in that of another, in every case as 
an end and never as a means.** Here the fundamental worth 
of every individual is affirmed. Our actions should not bo 
such as to use individuals as means for our ends, but rather 
to serve others as ends in themselves. 

Thus, for Kant, there is imbedded in the human reason 
itself a law which is so basic and fundamental that it directs 
all moral activity. It demands that everyone act at all times 
as though he were the ruling monarch of the universe and 
the principle of his action would automatically become the 
principle of the action of everyone. If each individual meas- 
ures a proposed act by this categorical imperative, he wiH 
be able to say without question whether it is right or wrong. 

The Views of Fichte and Schopenhauer 
FICHTE based his entire philosophic theory upon Kantfs 
idea of a moral nature in man which has the right to make 
certain definite demands. Starting with the moral nature of 



96 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

man, he built a philosophy which would satisfy the de- 
mands of this nature. 

This moral law, likewise, implies, Fichte taught, the 
existence of a moral world order in which man can trust. 
Having the moral law within himself, man is justified in 
assuming that the world is such that the demands of this 
law can be met 

Therefore, man must become intelligent, must know what 
is right and do it because it is right. The ignorant man can- 
not be good. Being free, not forced by some outside au- 
thority, man must know the moral law and its implica- 
tions, and must at aH times govern himself accordingly. 
Mere respect for the moral law is not enough. Man must 
act. Therefore morality, goodness, is not a state to be at- 
tained once and for all, a condition of eternal blessedness, 
but is a continuous struggle of the intelligent individual to 
act in every situation so as to meet the requirements of the 
moral law. Knowledge is a necessary part of morality for 
Fichte. 

SCHOPENHAUER begins with an affirmation of the will as 
fundamental to the universe. Kanfs thing-in-itself, the 
source of all our impressions, is will, Schopenhauer says. 
This will to be, will to live, is the cause of all the struggle in 
the world and thus of all evil and suffering. A world where 
blind wiUs are straggling with each other to live, where the 
more powerful fall and devour the less powerful that they 
may live, is a world of evil. Will to live begets selfishness. 
Each individual will struggle to preserve himself despite 
what happens to others. 

Thus, for Schopenhauer, sympathy or pity is basic to 
morality. To the degree that one has sympathy for others, 
he will act not for himself but for them, and thus be good. 
The way to this good life is through denial of the in- 
dividual will; self-sacrifice brings happiness and peace. And 
this can be attained if we stop to realize that every in- 
dividual is actually part of the whole, the universal will. 
The one against whom we struggle is actually part of the 
whole of which we are also members. When we reach this 



WHAT IS GOOD AND WHAT IS EVIL? 97 

understanding, we will stop struggling and will develop 
sympathetic understanding. 

According to Mitt, Bentham> and Spencer 

Recent philosophic thought regarding the problem of 
good and evil has been concerned with man's social re- 
lationships. It has been an ethics of the human group 
rather than that of divine laws. Consequently, it has taken 
on the tinge of relativity. Goodness and evil become quali- 
ties of acts relative to the situation in which they are per- 
formed. 

JOHJST STUART MILL is a good representative of the 
Utilitarian school in his contention that the measure of 
good is in terms of "the greatest good of the greatest num- 
ber." One must ask of an act, Will it bring much good to a 
great number of individuals? This eliminates selfishness 
and makes the criterion of good the social consequences 
of the proposed act. 

Further, Mill holds that "goods* differ in quality and 
that the goods of the intellect are better than the goods of 
the senses. Therefore, not only is the social factor empha- 
sized, but also emphasis is placed upon the nature of the 
act 

JEBEMY BENTHAM is very dose to Mill in his thinking 
about good and evil. He too bases good upon the Utili- 
tarian principle of "the greatest good of the greatest num- 
ber.* But he does not admit that goods differ in quality. 
His only criterion is the number of individuals affected by 
the act Bentham justifies this position on the basis of self- 
interest, holding that to so act will actually bring the great- 
est good to the one acting. 

In this modern treatment of the subject, good and bad 
are not written in the nature of the universe, but are deter- 
mined by social factors. The emphasis is placed upon the 
consequences of one's act in the experiences of others. The 
idea of a God setting down absolutely defined moral laws 
is gone. Also the idea that an evil act angers God while a 
good act makes Him happy is missing. Here is a relative 
morality, and the determiner of good and bad is the effect 



98 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

of the act upon the lives of other human individuals now 
living or to live in the future. 

HERBERT SPENCER attacks the problem from the point of 
view of the scientist and seeks to discover a scientific basis 
for right and wrong in conduct at large. From the point of 
view of evolution, conduct is a developing, evolving thing, 
a matter of adjustment of acts to ends. For him, the most 
highly developed conduct, and therefore the best, is that 
which makes living richer for the individual and for those 
among whom he lives and those who will come after him. 

The social group, for Spencer, is the ultimate end of 
morality. Goodness is to be determined in those terms. But 
he distinguishes between conduct that is absolutely right 
and that which is relatively right. Absolutely right conduct 
is that which is immediately pleasurable and at the same 
time produces future happiness for the individual and the 
group. Relative right is productive of future happiness, but 
is not immediately pleasurable. The goal is, of course, ab- 
solute right 

The Ethical Views of James and Dewey 

The social and individual consequences of activity are 
emphasized by philosophers of the Pragmatic school as 
criteria of good and evil. Both WILLIAM JAMES and JOHN 
DEWEY, especially Dewey, are emphatic at this point. The 
good is that which serves the ends of the group and the 
individual in the group. A good act is one which considers 
the individual as an end in himself and not as a means. But, 
by so considering each individual, we consider the welfare 
of the group. The human individual, as a social unit, is the 
ultimate measure of good and evil. That which enriches his 
life must necessarily enrich the lives of all. Here the indi- 
vidual and the group are tied together, since, it was argued 
by Dewey, individuality is. a social product and no one 
has true individuality save as a member of the group. 

Thus, a survey of the thinking of men down the ages 
about good and evil reveals two fundamental positions and 
many shades of both. On the one hand measures of good 
and evil are thought to be inherent in the nature of the 



WHAT IS GOOD AND "WHAT IS EVIL? Q9 

universe. Man is to discover them by coming to an under- 
standing of the universe and its nature. Whether the uni- 
verse speak to man with its own voice, or whether the 
voice be that of the Creator of the universe, the position 
is fundamentally the same. Good and bad are absolute, 
having been established from the beginning of time, and 
apply in all situations and at all times. When the criteria 
have been discovered, either by rational searching of the 
universe or by revelation, they are forever true, never 
changing. 

The other position is that good and bad are relative 
terms, and that the measures, the criteria, are to be dis- 
covered by a study of the particular situation involved. 
Time and place are determiners of good and evil. For a 
sick man, certain foods are evil, but for a well man they 
are good. In a modern social group, preservation of the 
aged and weak is good, but in a primitive group which is 
beset by enemies and must be on the move to escape de- 
struction, to preserve the aged and infirm is bad since it 
slows down the group and may result in disaster. This 
position looks at the consequences of the particular act in 
terms of the life of society and determines the ethical 
quality of the act in terms of the good of the whole. 

Man's thought on matters of ethics has taken these two 
lines throughout history, the absolute and the relative. 
And, among present-day thinkers both positions are to be 
discovered, although the relative point of view is the most 
pronounced. It is difficult for modern man, possessed of 
great respect for science and human reason, to find ade- 
quate ground for an absolute theory of right and wrong. 
All the evidence which commands his respect seems to 
point away from this to a relative position. 



Chapter IV 
THE NATURE OF GOD 

HESIOD XENOPHANES PLATO AJUSTOTLE 

PL01TNUS AUGUSTINE AQUINAS 
ECKHABT BKUNO BOEKME BACON 
SPINOZA LOCKE BERKELEY HUME 
KANT SCHELLING SCHLE1ERMACHER 
SPENCEH BRADLEY JAMES DEWEY 



What is the nature of God, and how is he related to 
the universe? Is God a person, like man but more 
ideal? Or is God a name for the force or forces which 
have brought the universe into being and sustain it? 
Can the human mind know God, or is God so far 
above man that nothing can be known about him? 
What is God's relation to us? 



The idea of gods came before the idea of God. The 
earliest peoples known did not think of* there being only 
one god but rather believed in numerous gods: gods of 
trees, rivers, winds, the sky, the earth, and hundreds of 
others. In some cases one god was more powerful than the 
others, but he was one of many. 

As mankind developed, belief centered on a few power- 
ful gods who were looked upon as ruling the more impor- 
tant areas of life. The other gods were reduced to the state 
of lesser spirits, elves, or beings very much like men but 
with more power than men. 

The early Hebrews were among the first to conceive of 



THE NATOBE OF GOD 1O1 

there being one god and to eliminate all other gods. But 
this conception was not won easily. We are told in the 
Bible that Moses introduced the Hebrews to this one god 
when he delivered the Ten Commandments to his people 
from Mount Sinai Gradually the people came to believe 
in this god, whom they called Jehovah, and to ascribe to 
him all the power and influence which had belonged to the 
many gods of their early history. 

When we first hear of tie Greeks they were believers in 
many gods. As they became more civilized, some of the 
gods of their fathers were forgotten and the few who were 
left were thought of as constituting a community very 
much like the human community except that it was more 
ideal. 

At the head of this community was Zeus who ruled as a 
sort of super king. On his throne with. him, sat his wife, 
Hera. Zeus was a glorified man with all the weaknesses of 
men* all human passions and defects, but also with many 
human virtues. Among the other gods were individuals 
with specific duties and specific areas of power. There were 
Apollo, Hermes, Aphrodite, and many others, principally 
offspring of Zeus. The divine community was full of jeal- 
ousies, bickerings, intrigue, and other human frailties. But 
the early Greeks feared and worshiped these divinities. 

This is known as the period of mythology in Greek his- 
tory. Behind it the record is dim and uncertain. No one 
knows where these ideas about the gods came from. It is 
believed, however, that they were originally conceived as 
forces or spirits concerned with various phases of life in 
the environment of the ancient Greeks and their ancestors. 

HESIOD, a Greek writer about whom we know very little, 
wrote a Theogony or book of the gods in which he at- 
tempted to account for things and the coining of the gods. 
He taught that in the beginning was Chaos who gave birth 
to Gaea, the earth, and Eros, love. Then Chaos gave birth 
to Erebos, darkness, and Nyx, night. These two were 
united and gave birth to Aether, light, and Hemera, day. 
The earth begot Pontus, the sea, and, in union with the 
heaven, Uranos, begot Chronos, time. 



Chapter IV 
THE NATURE OF GOD 

HESIOB XENOPHANES PLATO ARISTOTLE 

PLOTINUS AUGUSTINE AQUINAS 
ECKHART BRUNO BOEHME BACON 
SPINOZA LOCKE BERKELEY HUME 
KANT SOTDELLING SCBOLEIERMACHER 
SPENCER BRADLEY JAMES DEWEY 



What is the nature of God, and how is he related to 
the universe? Is God a person, like man but more 
ideal? Of is God a name for the force or forces which 
have brought the universe into being and sustain it? 
Can the human mind know God 9 or is God so far 
above man that nothing can be known about him? 
What is Gods relation to us? 



The idea of gods came before the idea of God. The 
earliest peoples known did not think of there being only 
one god but rather believed in numerous gods: gods of 
trees, rivers, winds, the sky, the earth, and hundreds of 
others. In some cases one god was more powerful than the 
others, but he was one of many. 

As mankind developed, belief centered on a few power- 
ful gods who were looked upon as ruling the more impor- 
tant areas of life. The other gods were reduced to the state 
of lesser spirits, elves, or beings very much like men but 
with more power than men. 

The early Hebrews were among the first to conceive of 



THE NATDBE OF GOD 1O1 

there being one god and to eliminate aH other gods. But 
this conception was not won easily. We are told in the 
Bible that Moses introduced the Hebrews to this one god 
when he delivered the Ten Commandments to his people 
from Mount Sinai. Gradually the people came to believe 
in this god, whom they called Jehovah, and to ascribe to 
hi all the power and influence which had belonged to the 
many gods of their early history. 

When we first hear of the Greeks they were believers in 
many gods. As they became more civilized, some of the 
gods of their fathers were forgotten and the few who were 
left were thought of as constituting a community very 
much like the human community except that it was more 
ideal. 

At the head of this community was Zeus who ruled as a 
sort of super king. On his throne with him, sat his wife, 
Hera. Zeus was a glorified man with all the weaknesses of 
men, all human passions and defects, but also with many 
human virtues. Among the other gods were individuals 
with specific duties and specific areas of power. There were 
Apollo, Hermes, Aphrodite, and many others, principally 
offspring of Zeus* The divine community was full of jeal- 
ousies, bickerings, intrigue, and other human frailties. But 
the early Greeks feared and worshiped these divinities. 

This is known as the period of mythology in Greek his- 
tory. Behind it the record is dfm and uncertain. No one 
knows where these ideas about the gods came from. It is 
believed, however, that they were originally conceived as 
forces or spirits concerned with various phases of life in 
the environment of the ancient Greeks and their ancestors. 

HESIOD, a Greek writer about whom we know very little, 
wrote a Theogony or book of the gods in which he at- 
tempted to account for things and the coming of the gods. 
He taught that in the beginning was Chaos who gave birth 
to Gaea, the earth, and Eros, love. Then Chaos gave birth 
to Erebos, darkness, and Nyx, night. These two were 
united and gave birth to Aether, light, and Hemera, day. 
The earth begot Pontus, the sea, and, in union with the 
heaven, Uranos, begot Chronos, time. 



102 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CTEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

If we are to believe Hesiod, the early Greek gods were 
things of the universe conceived of as alive, as beings very 
much like humans* By the time of the first Greek philoso- 
phers these ideas had been organized into the Greek re- 
ligion in which the vast majority of the people believed 
completely. Temples were erected to the gods and there 
had grown up a whole class of people devoted to conduct- 
ing worship before the altars of these gods. They claimed 
to understand the gods better than the laymen and gave 
advice to the people as to how they might keep the 
gods happy and win their favor and help in various 
undertakings* 

The Views of ike Early Greek TMosophers 

When the Greek philosophers began to write and teach, 
they did not attempt to overthrow the gods or to question 
them directly. Most of the early philosophers believed in 
the gods as the popular mind and tradition conceived 
them. However, they did seek to account for the existence 
of diings in ways different from the gods. TBALES, for ex- 
ample, sought to explain the coming of the world and all 
other things in natural ways and without appeal to divine 
beings. Although ANAXEMANDEH taught that the original 
substance from which everything came was *the infinite,* 
he did not tie this idea up with the popular belief about 
the gods. 

Nevertheless, there was always in the back of the think- 
ing of these early philosophers the hovering belief that the 
original creation and the ordering of the universe were re- 
sults of the working of God. We find them often referring 
to God as the source of the original stuff of the universe 
and as the power which in some way established the order 
of the universe. However, these philosophers are never very 
clear about this point It is highly possible that most of 
these men were deeply religious and were attempting to 
carry their religion in one basket and their philosophy in 
another and often getting the contents of the two baskets 
mixed up in their thinking. 
HERACLITUS, however, had a deep contempt for the re- 



THE NATURE OF GOD 1O3 

ligion of the masses and did not hesitate to write, ~And to 
these images they pray, just as if one were to converse 
with men's houses, for they know not what gods and heroes 
are." No doubt Heraelitus believed that he did know what 
gods and heroes were. 

XENOPHANES, a rhapsodist and philosophical poet of the 
sixth century B.C., attacked the popular religious beliefe 
of his day and countered them by proclaiming that God 
was one and unchangeable. He was extremely bitter in 
condemning the popular idea that the gods were like mor- 
tals. "Yes/* he wrote, *and if oxen or lions had hands, and 
could paint with their hands and produce works of art as 
men do, horses would paint the forms of gods like horses 
and oxen like oxen* Each would represent them with bodies 
according to the form of each* 3 * And in another place he 
says, "So the Ethiopians make their gods black and snub- 
nosed; the Thracians give theirs red hair and blue eyes." 

In place of these beliefs about gods, which seemed crude 
to him, Xenophanes taught that God is unlike human be- 
ings in every way. God is one who governs the universe 
without any effort He lives in one place and never moves. 
He is a whole, without beginning or ending, an eternal 
unity. As a whole, God does not move; but his parts do 
move. 

For Xenophanes, God is thought of as the fundamental 
principle of tie universe. God is the world, the whole of 
living nature. Thus Xenophanes holds to a dear pantheism, 
a belief that everything in the universe is God, and God is 
everything in the universe. God is the "One and All." For 
him there is only one God, and this God is the universe. As 
the universe, God is a whole, a unity, One. But within the 
universe, within God, there are many parts which change 
place with each other while the whole changes not. Xe- 
nophanes discards the popular polytheism or belief in the 
existence of many gods for a more advanced monotheism 
or belief in one god. 

Thus, it is dear that during the pre-Sophist period of 
Greek philosophy the popular religion with its many gods 
was being countered with a more philosophic conception 



104 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CTEAT FffiELOSOPHEBS 

of one god, the source in some way of the entire universe 
and the power behind aH the phenomena o the universe. 
Further, the popular idea of the gods and beings much like 
men had been challenged by the idea that the one God 
was very different from man ia every respect. 

This spirit of challenge reached a high point during the 
period of the Sophists. These practical teachers of young 
men made it their business to attack and challenge every- 
thing, and belief fa the gods did not escape. They appealed 
to reason and pointed out constantly that the popular be- 
lief in many gods was not reasonable. Although their work 
was destructive of the generally accepted beliefs, it was 
most valuable, since it made men think seriously about 
their beliefs in an effort to meet the objections offered by 
the Sophists. It became necessary for thinkers to ask them- 
selves the question, What is the true conception of God? 
And out of this qpiestioning there arose a more consistent 
and purer conception of the nature of God. 

The Concept of Godfathe Thought of Socrates, 
Plato, and Aristotle 

One of those who sought to develop a more consistent 
and purer conception of God was SOCRATES, but he paid 
the price of a pioneer in that the masses misunderstood 
him, thought he was destroying belief fa the gods, and 
condemned him to death for his impiety. 

His pupil, PLATO, uses the word God, but in a very con- 
fused way. Often one feels that he is fhfaVfng of the gods 
just as the masses think of the***!, as beings governing 
different areas of the universe. Indeed, the popular con- 
ceptions of the gods are strewn through his works. At other 
times Plato seems to teach the existence of one supreme 
God who is master and ruler of the entire universe. La his 
book, the Tisnaeus, he accounts for the creation of the uni- 
verse by using a Demiurge, or sort of architect, who takes 
already-created ideas and matter and moulds the universe. 
In another place we find him speaking of the Creator as 
the source of souls. 

This leads us to conclude that Plato believed in the ex- 



THE NATUBK OF GOD 10$ 

istence of many gods, each of which he thought to be 
much like a human souL Among these gods are the idea 
of the Good, the whole world of ideas, the Demiurge, the 
world soul, souls of the planets, and aH tie gods of the 
popular religion. However, on this matter of gods Plato is 
never clear. Perhaps Plato was attempting to xrse the pop- 
ular beliefs to teach more profound truths. In some pas- 
sages we are led to believe that he did not attempt to 
account for the coming into being of either the world of 
ideas or matter, but takes them as existing from the be- 
ginning. Nor does he seek to explain the source of the 
Demiurge* He also existed from the beginning. Given the 
Demiurge, ideas, and matter, Plato goes on to teach that 
the Demiurge, using ideas and matter, created aH the gods 
in whom the masses believed. 

In other passages, however, Plato speaks of God as the 
creator of everything in the universe and the goal of all 
human life as well as the life of all nature. Holding that the 
spirit of man is like God and that the body is a prison of 
the soul, he writes that *we ought to fly away from earth 
as quickly as we can, and to fly away is to become like 
God.** Here he seems to border on mysticism. 

The thinking of ARISTOTLE is much clearer on this point 
than is that of Plato. You wiH remember from our previous 
discussions that Aristotle believed that there were two 
causes in the universe, form and matter. For him forms 
are forces which realize themselves in the world of matter 
just as the idea of the artist realizes itself in marble. Hence 
the form is the cause of motion. Matter moves because of 
form. 

Indeed, Aristotle shows traces of the old Greek idea that 
matter was alive. Not only does form, which is within mat- 
ter, move matter, but matter seeks to become or realize the 
form. For example, the oak tree is the f onn and the acorn 
is the matter. The acorn grows into the oak tree, it realizes 
the form "oak tree* which was in it as an acorn but un- 
realized. As it is growing, according to Aristotle, it is striv- 
ing to become an oak tree. This is its motion. 

But, before the acorn there was matter and an idea or 



1O6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

form "acorn." This form was in matter, and matter was 
striving to become an acofn because of the presence of the 
form in it One might go on tracing this series of events 
from the crudest matter, each step through the oak tree 
and beyond, realizing that at each point there is matter 
and form, and matter striving to become form, being 
moved by form. Is this series continuous forever? 

Aristotle said, "No." At the end there is pure form, form 
without matter, and he called this an eternal "unmoved 
mover, 5 * the ultimate cause of all motion, of all becoming 
in the universe. This "God" is the cause of motion, but does 
not move himself. How is this possible? 

We have all had the experience of knowing a person, a 
hero to us, whom we wanted to be like. We have fash- 
ioned our lives after him and have grown into his likeness. 
Hawthorne's immortal story, The Great Stone Face, is il- 
lustrative of this experience. The little boy looked at the 
face so much that he came to be like it But the face was 
not moved. It did not change. So with Aristotle's "un- 
moved mover," it moves men, it draws matter, but does not 
move itself, is not affected. 

All the universe, every object and being in it, desires to 
realize itself because of God. His existence is the ultimate 
cause of their striving. Thus, God is the center toward 
which all things strive, and therefore he is the unifying 
principle of the universe. Every possibility, form, is realized 
in him. 

Aristotle's God is the ideal of the philosopher, since he is 
all that the philosopher strives to be, pure intelligence. 

The Position of the Later Greek Thinkers 

While Aristotle was a monist, a believer in one God, the 
Epicureans were polytheists, believers in many gods. They 
believed that the gods existed and were shaped like men, 
but were far more beautiful. Their bodies were believed 
to be fine bodies of light. The Epicureans also believed 
that the gods differed in sex, needed food, and spoke the 
Greek language. 

But the gods of the Epicureans were very different from 



1HE NATDBE OF GOD 1O7 

what the masses thought. The gods did not create the 
world, were not interested in men, were perfect, did not 
interfere with the world at all. They lived a peaceful, 
happy, contented life, free from all the cares and worries 
which men know. 

For the Stoics there is one God, related to the world just 
as the soul is related to the human body. God is corporeal, 
bodily, but a body of extraordinary fineness. The Stoics be- 
lieved that all the forces in the universe were united into 
one force which penetrated everything, the soul of the 
universe. All life, all movement stems from this soul. This 
is God. This doctrine, of course, is pantheism, the belief 
that everything in the universe is God. In God is to be 
found the whole universe, just as all of the flower is con- 
tained in the seed. 

This God of the Stoics is very different from the gods of 
the Epicureans. He is the father of aH things, is one, and 
is not divided; he loves man and knows all that is going to 
happen, he punishes the evil and rewards the good. The 
Stoic God is very interested in the world of men. God lives 
at the farthest circle of the universe, and, from there, per- 
vades the whole universe, the Stoics believed, just as the 
soul is situated in a particular place in the body but per- 
vades the whole of the body. 

CABNEADES, one of the Skeptics, attacked this Stoic idea 
of God, showing its inconsistencies. He denied that the 
human reason is able to know God at all, and cannot even, 
know that God exists. We must be skeptical about the 
matter, he argued. 

The Greco-Religions Ideas About God 

When PHILO, and his Jewish-Greek contemporaries, ap- 
peared on the philosophical scene, the conception of God 
became paramount in philosophy. Philo, for example, came 
from the great Hebrew religious tradition, a tradition at the 
center of which was the idea of one all-good and all- 
powerful God. He brought this tradition into contact with 
Greek philosophy, and sought to show that it was consist- 
ent with the best in Greek thought 



108 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

For Philo, God is so far above man in greatness, good- 
ness, power, and perfection that we cannot know what he 
is. But we can be certain that he exists. Philo taught that 
God is the source of everything, is absolutely good, per- 
fect, blessed. Being so exalted, God cannot come in contact 
with matter. But he gives off, as light from a candle, be- 
ings or powers which combine in one power which he 
called the ""Logos" or divine Wisdom. This Logos created 
the universe, and is the intermediary between God and the 
world. Here God is separated from the world, a sharp dis- 
tinction being made between the all-pure God and the im- 
pure world of matter, the world in which we live. 

For PLOTTNUS, who attempted very much the same 
things as did Philo, God is the source of everything in the 
universe. But, God is so perfect that we cannot affinn any- 
thing about htm. We can say what he is not, but can 
never say what be is. Anything that we think about him is 
too poor to be true of hfrn- He is far above anything we 
can think. 

Further, as with Philo, God created the world not di- 
rectly, but by means of emanations, beings coming from 
him but not him. God, for Plotinus, is like an infinite stream 
which flows out but is never exhausted. The world de- 
pends upon God, but God does not need the world. 

Creation, for Plotinus, is a fall from God. At the bottom 
of creation is pure matter, the farthest thing from God. 
Here, again, we note the shaip division between God and 
the world, pure God and impure world. 

The Early and Medieval Christian Conception of Cod 

Christianity, as we have already seen, began very early 
in its history to feel the effects of Greek philosophy. The 
Gospel of John, written about 100 AJX, shows very defi- 
nitely this influence. The book begins with a distinctly 
Greek doctrine, the doctrine of the Logos or world spirit 
which emanates from God and creates the world. 

As Christianity grew and influenced more and more tibe 
Greek and Roman world, it became necessary to bring in a 
great deal of Greek philosophy. Thus, the Apologists arose 



THE NATUBE OF GOD ICQ 

to attempt a joining of Christianity and Greek thought 
They taught that the order and reason in the universe 
point to the existence of a First Cause, a being who is the 
source of everything, is good, and is eternal. This First 
Cause, or God, is the eternal principle in all changing 
things. He emits the Logos as the sun emits light, and 
through the Logos created the universe. 

God, for the Apologists, is pure reason personified, 
thought of as a person. Thus, for them, Reason is the un- 
derlying principle of the universe, its cause and directing 
and controlling force. 

In the teaching of SAINT AUGUSTINE the vast difference 
between God and the world is emphasized. God is eternal, 
is transcendent, all good, all wise, absolute in every way. 
He is the cause of everything, the creator of the universe 
out of nothing. Further, Augustine taught that God, in the 
beginning, predetermined everything, so that he knew from 
the first what would happen to all his creatures throughout 
eternity. 

The God of Augustine is the idealization of everything 
that man considers good and worthy. He is absolute power, 
perfect goodness, the source and creator of everything. He 
knows everything and has so controlled the universe that 
everything is determined by him forever. 

For several centuries the idea of God held by the Chris- 
tian Church remained very much like that of Saint Augus- 
tine. JOHN SCOTUS EKIGENA taught that God was the source 
of all things, but went somewhat further than Augustine 
when he took the position that God and his creation are 
one. For him, God is in the world, the world is God, but 
God is also more than the world; he is the world plus. The 
world, Erigena held, is only a slight revelation of God who 
is far more than all the universe. 

By this view, Erigena is able to hold with the Church 
that God is perfect goodness, power, wisdom, and is never 
wholly known by men. Man may know something about 
God from looking at his universe, but this is only a small, 
insignificant part of God. Indeed, for this early thinker, 
God is in reality unknowable and ^indefinable. Man cannot 



11O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHEBS 

expect, with his little brain, to understand God or to com- 
prehend his ways. 

As Christianity developed during the first centuries of the 
Christian era, a very difficult problem came to the fore* 
God, as we have seen, was conceived as pure, holy, per- 
fect. Thus ft became necessary to introduce an intermediate 
being, the Logos, to account for the creation of the trai* 
verse* Many thinkers identified this being with Christ. Fur- 
ther, Christian thinkers held that there was a Spirit or 
power of divine origin permeating the universe, the Holy 
Spirit 

As philosophers straggjed with the problem of the na- 
ture of God, they found it necessary to account for the ex- 
istence of the Logos, Christ, and the Holy Spirit Some 
theory of their relationship with each other and with God 
had to be developed. Out of the thinking on this problem 
came the conception of the Trinity. God is thought of as 
One, a Unity, a Whole. But he is also Three: God, the 
Logos or Christ, and the Holy Spirit 

The Apologists taught that both the Logos and the Holy 
Spirit were emanations from God and that Jesus Christ was 
the Logos in the form of a man. Consequently, they held 
that although God is One, he is also Three Persons. The 
Godhead is a Unity, but expresses itself in the world as 
the creative Logos or Christ and as divine reason which 
permeates everything* 

A little later there came into prominence a group of 
thinkers, the Medalists, .who maintained that all three per- 
sons or the Trinity are actually God in three forms or 
modes. The Logos is actually God creating; the Holy Spirit 
is actually God reasoning; and God is actually God being. 
This led to a prolonged discussion as to whether the Logos 
was of like nature with God or was of the same substance 
as God. Is the Logos an emanation from God or is it God 
in another form? 

Augustine held to the orthodox conception of the Trinity. 
He believed that God was One, but expressed himself in 
the universe as three persons, emanations. This was known 
as the Athanasian position from the fact that ATHANASIUS, 



THE NATURE OF GOD 111 

the leader of a group of early Christian thinkers, developed 
the point of view. According to Athanasius, Christ is the 
principle of salvation and was begotten, not made, by the 
Father, God. He is eternal with the Father, and is of the 
same substance as the Father. Further, He shares the full 
nature of the Father. la Jesus this Logos or Christ was 
united with a human body. The Holy Ghost, he main- 
tained, was a third being. Thus the one Godhead was con- 
ceived to be a Trinity of the same substance, three persons 
of the same nature: Father, Son, and Holy Ghost. 

ROSCELBST, one of the first Nominalists, applied the doc- 
trine of Nominalism to the Trinity. He argued that single 
things were the only realities and that universal, or gen- 
eral concepts, were mere names or words. Consequently, 
he held that there could be no reality corresponding to the 
name God. But there are only three different substances or 
persons equal in power. Thus, for him, the Trinity is not 
One in Three, but is three distinct beings. 

This was a denial of the orthodox official doctrine and 
drew great opposition from the Church. It became evident 
to the Church officials that preservation of the Trinity as a 
doctrine of the Church rested upon adoption of the Realist 
position, the position that Universals are the only reals and 
that individuals are forms of the universal Thus, this posi- 
tion became the dominant one among the Scholastics, the 
foundation upon which was built a great deal of the intel- 
lectual and ecclesiastical structure of the Middle Ages. 

The work of ANSELM hinged largely on the idea that 
universals exist independently of particular objects. On the 
basis of this idea he argued for the existence of God. He 
taught that the idea of God as a being who exists implies 
that God must exist. If God did not exist, the idea would 
not be the idea of the greatest thing thinkable. Man could 
still think of something greater, something that did exist 
Thus, the perfection of God, the idea of a perfect being, 
he held, implies the existence of God, because perfection 
must include existence. 

This argument, of course, could not be made to hold up, 
as many thinkers have shown. The mere idea of a thing> 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHELOSOPHEBS 

an idea which includes the concept of existence, does not 
guarantee that there is an object which exists. GAUOTLO, 
a theologian of the times, showed that one might have an 
idea of a peri ect island without any proof that the island 
existed. 

In his Theology,* ABEXABD taught that the Trinity con- 
sists of the Father, who is One or Goodness, the Holy 
Ghost or World Soul, and the Logos or the mind of God. 
He also taught that tibe three persons of the Trinity are the 
power, good will, and wisdom of God. 

While these thinkers were attempting to make religion a 
rational system, and God, at least in part, understandable, 
there was another movement which despaired of under- 
standing God. This was known as Mysticism. For Mysti- 
cism, God is not so much to be known as experienced. We 
do not understand Him with our minds, but we come into 
direct contact with Him through a mystical experience. 
God is reached by contemplation. This approach to God 
gives one an understanding of Him which no amount of 
reasoning can ever reach, so argued BICHABD OF ST. Vic- 
TOB* Hie goal of the mystic is "the mysterious ascension of 
the soul to heaven, tibe sweet home-coming from the land 
of bodies to the region of spirit, the surrender of the self in 
and to God/* But, this absorption into God is not some- 
tiling which man can attain of his own will All a man can 
do is to prepare through certain exercises for this "plunge 
into the ocean of infinite truth/* Then he must wait. If God 
favors him, He wiH permit him to make the plunge. 

THOMAS AQUINAS was influenced greatly by the thinking 
of Aristotle, and he sought to adjust Aristotle and Christian 
theology to each other without destroying the fundamental 
doctrines of the Church. Indeed, he believed that the 
teachings of Aristotle could be made to support these doc- 
trines. 

God, said Aquinas, is pure form. We infer His existence 
from the facts of His creation. For example, everything 
that moves must have a mover. We find movement in the 
universe. Therefore, the ultimate source of this movement 
must be an unmoved principle, the Unmoved Mover of 



SHE NATUIUS OF GOD 113 

Aristotle, or GodL Further, the universe reveals that things 
are related in a graduated scale of existence from the low- 
est forms of existence upward toward more or less perfect 
objects* This leads one to infer that there must be some 
thing that is perfect at the very summit^ God. 

God, for Aquinas, is the first and final cause of the uni- 
verse pure form or energy. He is absolutely perfect He is 
the source, the Creator of everything out of nothing. In 
this creation he has revealed Himself . Further, God rules 
the universe through his perfect will 

Aquinas, in developing this iheory of the nature of God, 
set the pattern for Catholic belief about God for all times. 
Even to the present the Catholic Church follows this posi- 
tion practically as outlined by Aquinas. 

The teaching of JOHN DXJNS Scores is very similar to 
that of Aquinas. God is pure form or pure energy. He is the 
cause of the universe, a cause that is conscious and has a 
purpose in creating and ruling the universe. He is infinite 
will which is completely free, so free that he can will or not 
will just as he wants. All this, Scotus argues, is to be proven 
from the experience which we have of the world about us. 

MEISTER ECEBAB.T, a mystic of the thirteenth and four- 
teenth centuries, taught that God is inconceivable, an in- 
definable spiritual substance, a something in which all 
things are United. As such, God cannot reveal himself but 
becomes known only through the Trinity. Constantly the 
Three Persons of the Trinity flow out of God and back into 
him. He is the ground of the universe. All things are in 
God, and God is in all things. I am God communicating 
himself. I am immanent in the essence of God. He works 
through me. As I return to God in the mystic experience, I 
become one with God again. 

Bruno, Boehme, and Other Forerunners of the "Renaissance 
As the Renaissance began to dawn, and men undertook 
to think themselves free from the long dominance of the 
Church and its doctrines, they became aware of the nu- 
merous inconsistencies in the doctrines of the Scholastics. 
They saw that some of the ideas about God held by these 



114 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

philosophers would not stand up under the impact of 
searching reason. However, although they attacked the 
reasoning of the Scholastics, they were unwilling to aban- 
don the idea of God. 

NICHOLAS OF CUSA, for example, held that man could 
have an immediate intuition of God, something resembling 
the mystic's experience. This experience solves the many 
contradictions and inconsistencies which appear in any at- 
tempt to think about God. Through reason we cannot 
Icnow God, but beyond reason is this Earned ignorance," 
this supersensible experience of God. 

GIORDANO BRUNO, fascinated by the immensity of the 
universe which the astronomy of his day was revealing, 
held that God is immanent in *hfo infinite universe, the 
principle of activity. He taugjit that he is the unity of all 
opposites in the universe, a unity without opposites, which 
the human mind cannot grasp. 

In this same tradition was the uneducated German mys- 
tic, JACOB BQEHMB, who taught that since God is the 
ground of everything, he is the union of all the opposites 
in the universe, the original source of all things. Through 
the objects of the universe God becomes conscious of him- 
self. A divine blind craving gives rise to the universe with 
aH its opposites. But in God all these opposites are united. 

The Position of Bacon, Hobbes, Descartes, and Pascal 

This despair of reason on the part of many as a means 
for reaching understanding of God was part of the trend 
toward freeing mankind from the bonds of the Church so 
that he could devote himself to the study of the world in a 
scientific manner. Theology and science were gradually 
separated, each taking its place in the scheme of things. 
Nevertheless, the endeavor to understand God continued, 
though the interpretations of God were in many instances 
very different from those of the Middle Ages. It became 
obvious that reason's God was very different from faith's 
God. Consequently, it happened many times that the phi- 
losopher's God was not the theologian's God. 

The position of FRANCIS BACON is a clear illustration of 



THE NATUBE OF GOD 11$ 

this development. He divided theology into the natural and 
the revealed. Natural theology, he taught, is that knowl- 
edge of God which we can get from the study of nature 
and the creatures of God. It gives convincing proof of the 
existence of God, but nothing more. Anything else must 
come from revealed theology. Here we must "quit the small 
vessel of human reason and put ourselves on board the 
ship of the church, which alone possesses the divine needle 
for justly shaping the course. The stars of philosophy will 
be of no further service to us. As we are obliged to obey 
the divine law, though our will murmurs against it, so we 
are obliged to believe in the word of God, though our rea- 
son is shocked at it/* 

THOMAS HOBBES, interpreting God in terms of his ma- 
terialistic philosophy, tells us that at the creation God gave 
motion to all things. Further, he suggests, God is body, a 
corporeal being, but of this he cannot be certain since he 
doubts that we can know what God is. We must limit our- 
selves to the assurance that God exists. However, Hobbes 
does speak of God as starting the universe in motion and of 
Him as ruling the world through the human rulers of the 
world. 

DESCABTES, through his method of reasoning, seeks to 
prove the existence of God and tell us a great deal about 
Him. He found the idea of God among his ideas, an idea 
of an absolutely real, perfect, infinite being. The cause of 
this idea, he argued, must be as real as the idea. There- 
fore God exists. The idea had to be placed in him by God, 
he held. This God is self-caused, is eternal, all-knowing, 
all-powerful, perfect goodness and truth, and the creator of 
all things. Nor will God deceive man. Whatever he has 
put into man is real, even the ideas which man finds in his 
thinking. 

Further, for Descartes, God is the basic substance of the 
universe and the two relative substances, mind and body, 
depend upon him. God gives motion to body. "God," he 
wrote, "originally created matter along with motion and 
rest, and now by his concourse alone preserves in the whole 



Il6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

the same amount of motion that he then placed in it. 7 * God 
is the "prime mover" o the universe, 

Descartes* conception o God is highly confusing and 
confused. He made God independent of Nature, thus rais- 
ing the problem of how God can impress himself upon 
Nature so that man can know anything about God. Fur- 
ther, how can God, as pure spirit, give motion to matter? 
This problem, among many others, was left to Descartes* 
followers- It was the problem of harmonizing the mechani- 
cal theory of the new science of the times with the the- 
ology of Christianity. 

BLAISE PASCAL attacked the problem and suggested that 
it was impossible for man to demonstrate the existence of 
God, that philosophic proofs were of no real value as re- 
gards God. We know God, he taught, only through reli- 
gious feeling. God is pure spirit and we can know him only 
through a spiritual experience. 

The Nature of God According to Spinoza 

It was SPINOZA who worked out what seemed then a 
masterful solution of the problem left by Descartes. For 
him God is the sole independent substance of the universe. 
Outside of God there can be no substance. Mind and body, 
thought and extension, are attributes of God and not inde- 
pendent of him. God is the cause of everything in the uni- 
verse. He is both thinking and extended substance. God 
is a thought in the human mind and he is a tree in the 
forest. Thus, God is all, and all is God. There is nothing 
outside of or independent of God. God is a single, eternal, 
infinite, self-caused principle of nature and of all things, 
God and the world are one. Here is clear pantheism. 

We can perceive only two attributes of God, thought 
and extension. We know God, then, through ideas and 
bodies. But this does not exhaust God. He is far more than 
this, and we can never know God completely. 

God, for Spinoza, is neither personality nor conscious- 
ness. He is not characterized by intelligence, feeling, or 
will. His actions are not directed by purpose; but all things 
follow from his nature according to strict law. All the ideas 



THE NATUBE OF GOD ll/ 

in the universe added together constitute the thinking of 
God. My thoughts and your thoughts, and the thoughts of 
everyone in the world, make up God's thoughts. 

Spinoza had sought to solve Descartes' problem by mak- 
ing God everything and more than everything. Mind and 
body are not two wholly different things, but are God seen 
in two different ways. Thus, God can influence both the 
world of thought and the world of things because actually 
he is both and is thus being himself. 

The Views of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Leibnitz 

With JOHN LOCKE a new attack was made on the prob- 
lem of the nature of God. True to his belief that we can 
have no innate ideas, Locke had to take the position that 
we cannot have an innate idea of God. However, he held 
that we may know about God if we use our natural abili- 
ties correctly. We can build the idea of God, he taught, 
out of other ideas which we have. If we take, for example, 
our ideas of existence, duration, power, pleasure, happi- 
ness, and the like, and think of these as extending to infin- 
ity and being gathered together, we will have an idea of 
God. God is, then, certain ideas which we have gathered 
from experience and extended to infinity. 

God, said Locke, most certainly exists. Man studies him- 
self and realizes that he must have been produced by some 
being who is greater than he. Thus, God is "real being,* 
thinks, is all-knowing, powerful, and just For Locke, God 
is spiritual substance, 1 a third substance in addition to mind 
and body. 

As creator of the world and man, God has established 
certain divine laws which man may discover through 
studying nature or through revelation. Further, God can 
enforce these laws either by punishments or rewards in 
this and in the next world even to eternity. Morality is 
based upon the will and laws of God, and only by know- 
ing his will and laws can one say whether or not a thing 
is right or wrong. 

GEOKGE BEBKEUSY, Bishop of Cloyne near the middle of 
the eighteenth century, took the position that God is the 
Supreme Spirit and the source of everything in the uni- 



Il8 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

verse. He argued that, on the basis of Locke's theory, one 
must admit that things exist only when they are perceived. 
But, to say that a table exists only when he perceived it, 
did not satisfy him. Consequently, he reasoned that al- 
though he might not be at the moment perceiving the 
table, God is perceiving it. Therefore, the table continues 
to exist as a thought in God's mind even though he left the 
room. The natural world is a creation of God's mind, is 
mental, and impresses our senses so that we have ideas, 
just as Locke had argued. God, then, is the cause of the 
natural world; however, this world is not material, it is 
spiritual, mental. 

In this way Berkeley believed he had solved the problem 
of Descartes and Spinoza. Both of those philosophers had 
struggled with the two things, mind and matter. Descartes 
taught that mind and matter were two secondary sub- 
stances coming in some way from the primary substance^ 
God. Spinoza argued that mind and matter were two as- 
pects, two ways of looking at the same substance, God. 
Berkeley eliminated matter by holding that God, spiritual 
substance, is all there is. That which we have thought to 
be matter is actually an idea in the mind of God. 

God, thus, is spiritual, the creator of everything in the 
universe through his own mind. The dualism of mind and 
matter which had worried philosophers since the begin- 
ning was eliminated. Matter is gone, and only mind re- 
mains. And we can operate on the principle that this 
Author of Nature will always act uniformly, although we 
cannot prove this since God is free to change his way of 
acting at any time he chooses. 

DAVID HUME was a skeptic. Consequently he sought to 
show that human reason cannot demonstrate the nature of 
God. All the arguments which past philosophers had used 
to prove the existence of God and his attributes were ex- 
amined by Hume and held to be faulty. Human reason, 
he held, is far too weak, blind, and limited to construct 
any adequate conception of God. 

However, Hume felt that one must believe in the exist- 
ence of God since such a belief is the basis of all human 



THE NATUBE OF GOD H9 

hopes, of morality, and of society. Since we find nothing 
in the universe existing without a cause, Hume argued, we 
may go on to the position that the cause of the universe 
must be God, a being of absolute perfection. But this can- 
not be proven by reason. Nor can we say anything about 
the nature or characteristics of God. 

Nevertheless, Hume suggests a probable way of think- 
ing of GodL It is possible, he said, that God is related to the 
world somewhat as the soul is related to the body, and is 
the active principle of the universe. But, he hastened to say, 
this is purely a probability. There is no proof of it which 
man can substantiate. 

Belief in God, Hume taught, does not come from man's 
reasoning but from human desire for happiness, fear of 
death and future misery, and the thirst on the part of 
many for revenge. Because we have these emotional and 
impulsive characteristics as human beings, we construct a 
belief in God and then seek to prove that such belief is 
justified by reason. Hume writes at length in his attempt 
to show that while, from the point of view of reason, we 
must be skeptical about God, from the fact of our impul- 
sive and emotional nature we do believe in God and con- 
struct a theory about God which is necessary for us. This 
approach to the problem of the nature of God was, as we 
shall see later, the part of Hume's philosophy which stimu- 
lated Immanuel Kant to make a distinction between pure 
reason and practical reason. 

In developing his theory of monads, LEIBNITZ took the 
position that these self-contained units of the universe are 
arranged in a continuous series of increasing clearness. At 
one extreme is the dullest monad, and at the other ex- 
treme is God, the highest and most perfect monad, pure 
activity, the "monad of monads." 

Further, God, for him, is the ultimate cause of every- 
thing. Although monads are shut off from everything and 
can in no way influence each other, God has so constructed 
the universe that each monad acts as though it were in- 
fluenced and were influencing. 

Man is unable to form a clear idea of God, since God is 



12O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHELOSOPHEKS 

the highest, most perfect monad and man is lower and less 
perfect Only another perfect monad could know God. 
However, man can have an idea of God by taking those 
qualities which he finds in himself, goodness, power, 
knowledge, and raising them to infinity. The result is the 
idea that God is infinite goodness, power, knowledge, and 
the like. 

Again, since God is perfect and complete, he cannot un- 
dergo change or development as do all other monads, He 
comprehends all things and all time at a glance and com- 
pletely. He created the world which is "the best of all 
possible worlds." 

The Concept of God in the Thought of Kant 

God, for IMMANCEL KANT, is the notion or highest Idea 
which man can have, the idea of the highest unity, of the 
one Absolute Whole including and encompassing every- 
thing. This idea transcends experience and cannot be ob- 
tained from experience. It is one of the results of reason 
which brings under one head all happenings. 

Kant insists that we must never forget that we have 
formed the idea of the whole of experience. It is nothing 
that we can know as we do one of our ideas arrived at 
through experience, for we cannot experience the whole 
universe. After we have formed this idea, we make an en- 
tity of this whole and personify it. Thus, for us it becomes 
God. 

Kant attacks the arguments for the existence of God ad- 
vanced by philosophers before Ttfm t seeking to prove that 
each one is full of inconsistencies and logical fallacies. But, 
although it is impossible for one to prove the existence of 
God by reason, belief in His existence is necessary for the 
moral life. We need this Idea of the Whole, this tran- 
scendent theology, as a foundation for our ethical prin- 
ciples. 

Although Kant criticizes the arguments of others for the 
existence of God, he offers his own argument, or proof, 
which he believes to be on a truer philosophical founda- 
tion than the others. He believed that each individual 



THE NATUEE OF GOD 

found inherent in reason itself the categorical imperative: 
"Always act so that you can will the maxim or determining 
principle of your action to become universal law; act so 
that you can will that everybody shall follow the principle 
of your action*'* This is a command that one live according 
to an absolutely good will Further, to live so is deserving 
of happiness. Thus, happiness and the good life should go 
together in the world. But they often do not We see good 
people very unhappy and very evil people happy. 

Consequently, there must be a God who is perfectly 
wise, good, and powerful to join happiness and goodness. 
God, for Kant, is able to know everything, is a Being who 
possesses our moral ideals, and has absolute power. 

Kant's theory, as you will recognize, is a further develop- 
ment of Hume's position. We cannot know by our reason 
that God exists or what he might be if he did exist No one 
can prove anything about God by argument or reasoning. 
But, we can, on the basis of our meager experiences, form 
an idea of the Whole of the universe and can personify it 
Further, we need the idea of God to serve as a foundation 
of our moral life. Kant called this idea of God "transcend- 
ent** since it transcends, goes beyond, experience. It is also 
a necessary idea, necessary for the living of the good life, 
for morality. 

This point of view is Kant's answer to skepticism. The 
philosophers, led by John Locke, had argued earnestly that 
man can know only that which he experiences. But man 
cannot experience God. At best, he can blow up or inflate 
his meager and small ideas to infinity and call that God- 
Kant agreed with those who held that we cannot know 
God through reason. But, he added, we need God. There- 
fore, reason can bring God back as a necessary unknown. 

Fichte, Schelling, Schleiermacher, Hegel, 
and Later German Thinkers 

Kant's influence reached deep into the thinking of those 
who followed. FICHTE came to the conclusion that the 
source of the universe was universal reason, intelligence 
alone, pure "ego." This ego is distinct from the self of each 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF CTEAT PHTLOSOPHEKS 

individual human being. It is the universal active reason 
which has created and cannot be kept from creating. This 
he called God. It is to be thought of as a "universal life- 
process" dominating the consciousness of every individual. 

Further, this universal ego or God is, for Fichte, the 
universal purpose of the universe and its existence is to be 
proven, as with Kant, by the moral law. Morality demands 
such a being, therefore God exists. 

The conception of God held by SCHEUJNG is very simi- 
lar to that of Fichte. Schefling teaches that God is to be 
understood as the creative energy which is the absolute 
ground of everything. This force or principle is the soul of 
the universe and is realized through the universe. Indeed* 
the theory held by Schelling is pure pantheism. The world 
is alive and it is alive because it is God and he is, of course,, 
alive. 

FRTFDRICH EBNST DANIEL SCHUEIERMACHER took the po- 
sition that God, the Absolute, and the world are one. For 
htm God has never in all time or eternity been without the 
world. Whenever God has been, the world has also been. 
Further, the world cannot be without God. Nevertheless, 
there is an important distinction to be made between God 
and the world. 

While God, for Schleiermacher, is to be thought of as a 
unity, a one, without space and time, the world is, as we 
conceive it, many things in space and in time. Thus, while 
this philosopher was in that school of thinking which we 
have called pantheism, he did make a distinction between 
God and the world. 

Further, he held that it is impossible to ascribe to God 
the usual attributes of personality, thought, will, and the 
like. For him, God is to be thought of as the universal 
creative force in the universe, the source of all life. He is 
such that man can know frfrn only through religious feeling, 
a feeling of absolute dependence. Man does, he argued, 
come to this feeling of dependence and recognizes that the 
thing upon which he is dependent for all that he is must 
be a "world ground," God. 

The theory of God as held by HEGEL is part of his 



THE NATURE OF GOD 123 

whole theory of evolution to which we have referred pre- 
viously. God, Hegel tells us, is Idea. By this he means that 
God must be thought of as the entire process of evolution, 
past, present, and future. The dialectical process which is 
unfolding in evolution is contained within God. (By "dia- 
lectic" or the "dialectical process" we mean the reasoning 
process.) 

Thus, God is the creative reason of the universe and re- 
veals himself in the world and as the world develops 
through evolution, he becomes self-conscious, comes to 
know himself more fully. In man he reaches the clearest 
self-consciousness. It is evident that Hegel's God is not 
complete, but is developing with the world. His is a de- 
veloping God. 

The world which RUDOLF HERMANN LOTZE believed in, 
a world of spiritual realities, could not, Lotze held, be 
thought of unless one admitted the existence of a universal 
substance of which all the spiritual units are modes or 
expressions. In this world of many interrelated units he saw 
the expression of some absolute will which unified these 
parts, which kept them from being all tangled up in endless 
confusion. All nature, then, is in some way controlled by 
the Absolute, a substance of which all the processes of 
nature are states. This, of course, is pantheism. 

We interpret this Absolute in terms of what we conceive 
as the highest and best possible. Thus, we think of it as 
a personality that is absolutely good, as a God of love. 

GUSTAV THEODOR FECHNER taught that God is to be 
thought of as the highest soul, a world soul, which is re- 
lated to the world just as the human soul is related to the 
human body. For Fechner, nature is the body of God. 
Fechner began his thinking from the fact of mental proc- 
esses which he discovered in men. The human individual 
thinks, he engages in what are called psychic processes. 
Also, according to Fechner, there are higher forms of 
psychic processes in the universe. All of these, united, are 
the world soul or God. 

This group of philosophers thought of God as the under- 
lying source or cause of the universe. He is, in some way, 



124 BASIC 'TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

that which is behind the universe. Some have told us that 
we can know fomi through our reason while others have 
held that reason is unable to penetrate behind the universe 
to its cause. A few Lave held that we can know God only 
through feeling. 

The Position of Comte, Spencer, and Bradley 

The later philosophers have tended to abandon the at- 
tempt to know God and turned the matter over to the 
theologians or religionists. AUGUSTS COMTE, as representa- 
tive of the Positivists, held that all attempts to get at the 
essence of things were symptoms of immature develop- 
ment of the human mind. When one reaches the stage of 
positivism he gives up all attempt to discover God and 
busies himself with discovering the relations which exist 
between things, phenomena. 

SIB WILLIAM HAMILTON held that one might believe in 
God if he wanted to do so, but that it is impossible for one 
to know anything about God since the ultimate must be 
unconditioned and the human mind can know only that 
which is conditioned by something else. 

HERBERT SPENCER argued that all we can know is that 
which is finite and limited. But we can relate things to an 
Absolute or something unrelated. However, we cannot 
know this Absolute, the substance which underlies all that 
we know. Therefore, the Absolute is, according to Spencer, 
the Unknowable. It exists. This he would not deny. But 
what it is, he argued that no one can know. 

F. H. BRADLEY disagrees with Spencer and maintains 
that the Absolute is knowable. Further, he holds tibat this 
Absolute is a harmonious system, a Whole which is in some 
way in every part of the universe. 

The Views of James and Dewey 

WILLIAM JAMES, true to his Pragmatism, holds that a 
belief in a God is necessary for the satisfaction of man's 
nature. We cannot prove that God exists, nor can we 
prove anything about him, but we have a will to believe 
in God, and we must satisfy this wilL 



THE NATUBE OF GOD 

The God in which James holds that man must believe is 
part of the universe, not divorced from it He is worldng 
with man in the realization of man's ideals, James speaks 
of him as man's great Companion, his helper. Often he 
speaks of God as a being very much like man,-~consciou$, 
personal, and good,-but somewhat more powerful than 
man. 

JOHN DEWEY would not use the term God without de- 
fining it in such a way that it ceases to have any real 
meaning. He recognizes that the universe exists and that 
men do have certain experiences which they have inter- 
preted in terms of God Dewey holds that such an inter- 
pretation carries with it too much that cannot be proven 
and, therefore, should not be made. 

Thus, man, in his thinking, has found himself within a 
universe which he does not understand and which deals 
out to him much that is evil in his sight. Man has at- 
tempted to account for this world and, at the same time, 
to save himself from the evil of the world. The result is 
many theories of God, the source of the universe and the 
salvation of man. 

From the earliest of men to the present we discover 
theories of how the universe came into being and con- 
tinues to function. Many of these theories are centered 
about a God or powerful being, very much like man but 
far greater, who created the universe, usually out of noth- 
ing. This God is often thought of as the force, principle, 
or power, which is working within the universe to keep it 
going. 

In many philosophies, as we have seen, this God is also 
more or less concerned about man. He offers man salva- 
tion from the world and its evils. He cares especially about 
man. 

The religious tradition has, with only a few exceptions, 
held to a more or less personal God who cares for man 
and who, at the same time, is the creator of the universe. 
Another tradition, the scientific, has not been so sure that 
there is anything in the universe which cares for man or 
that the creative force of the universe is anything like 



126 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHTLOSOPHEBS 

personality. Science knows forces, drives, energies in the 
universe, working and creating, and destroying. It sees 
man, with his values and hopes, coming into being as 
these forces operate and going to pieces as they continue 
to operate. Scientists will not dispute if someone wishes to 
give these forces a name and uses the name "God." But 
they are quick to state that the word ~God* must not be 
applied here with all its traditional connotations. 

Modern philosophy has been moving in the Direction of 
the scientists. Either it denies directly the existence of God 
and insists that the name be saved for the phenomenon in 
history to which it has been given originally, or it redefines 
the term so that it loses all its original meaning and be- 
comes merely a name for the forces of which the scientists 
speak Although there is a vast body of people who hold 
to a belief in the God as developed by Saint Augustine and 
Thomas Aquinas, and although there are some philoso- 
phers who hold to that position, the bulk of modern and 
present-day philosophy has abandoned the traditional 
Christian conception of God and put in its place a theory 
of the -Absolute either as the ground of the universe or the 
unity of the universe, a substance of which all else is 
created or just the universe taken as a whole and with its 
consistencies and likenesses emphasized. 

You and I are left to make our own choice from among 
these many theories. We may follow the tradition, or we 
may accept the scientific approach. 



Chapter V 
FATE VERSUS FREE WILL 

PYTHAGORAS SOCRATES PLATO ARISTOTLE 

BACON DESCARTES SPINOZA 

LOCKE HUME VOLTAIRE ROUSSEAU 

KANT SCHELLING HERBART SCHOPENHAUER 

MILL JAMES DEWEY 



Is- man free to mould Ms own destiny, or is Tie a mere 
straw in the wind of fate? Do our ideals, hopes, acts, 
end wills mean anything in the universe? Is it true, as 
some hold, that we come from the unknown, are buf- 
feted around by forces of which we have no control, 
and at last return to the unknown? 



The generally accepted belief that the life of the primi- 
tive man was free and happy is not supported by what is 
known about the ideas and thoughts of the earliest of 
men. The most general belief found among the most an- 
cient peoples is called "animism/* This is the belief that 
every object in the universe is actually a person very much 
like man himself but far more powerful. Further, early 
man was certain that many of these living objects were not 
friendly to him. 

This early man believed that the river, the mountain* 
each tree, the sun, moon, and each star, in fact everything 
in the universe was either a living being or else the home 
of a spirit. Each being or spirit was thought to be very 
powerful, jealous of this power, easily offended, and 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHEBS 

mighty in anger. Therefore the primitive man was con- 
stantly afraid lest he unwittingly offend and anger one of 
these beings or spirits and staffer the most fearful punish- 
ment. 

These beings and spirits ruled him at all times along 
with numerous other spirits which might be loose in the 
universe and rrnghfr enter frim at any time. Disease, mad- 
ness, and all the other disasters which might come to man 
were the workings of spirits within him, Thus primitive 
man's world, both inside and outside of himself, was 
swarming with beings and spirits who determined every- 
thing which he did or wiiich happened to him. 

In such a world of "powers and principalities* man was 
never free. That he might have or be a free will acting on 
his own never entered his mind. The beings and spirits 
of the universe directed and determined his every act and 
thought. 

Later mankind passed beyond belief in animism, but not 
to a belief in free will If the powers which governed all 
man's actions were not thought of as living objects in na- 
ture or spirits occupying natural objects and man himself, 
they were believed to be the Fates, beings of great power 
and influence who determined the destinies of every man. 
In the earliest Greek mythology we find the conception of 
the Fates, individuals weaving the web of destiny in which 
all mankind is caught and from which we cannot free 
ourselves. 

Both the idea of spirits and the idea of the Fates are 
expressions of a basic feeling among early peoples that in 
some way the destinies of each and every human being 
are determined by forces beyond ihe power of his control. 
It is the idea that all life is a consistent pattern determined 
by powers outside of man and to which man is completely 
and absolutely subject. Here no place is left for anything 
like free will on the part of man. Man is a marionette 
whose every action is controlled and determined by the 
pull of strings in the hands of powers far above and beyond 
him. He riiust follow their lead and can do nothing else. 



FATE VERSUS FREE "W3DLI* 



The Idea of Fate Among the Early Greek Thinkers 

Throughout Greek thought we discover the belief in the 
absolute power of the forces of the universe. Man's destiny 
is determined by these powers and, although he may not 
be happy about it, man is helpless. He must obey. 

The Pythagoreans were convinced that the universe, in- 
cluding man, was a closed system. This system could be 
understood if one understood the relations of the parts. 
Further, these relations could be expressed in terms of 
numbers* Consequently, if one could penetrate the secrets 
of numbers one would know the secrets of the universe and 
the destiny of man. This led to a careful study of numbers 
in an effort to predict man's future. 

In the thinking of PYTHAGORAS and his followers, the 
nature of the universe is such as to determine man's fate. 
The secrets of this fate are locked in numbers and can be 
unlocked if one understands the meaning of numbers. Con- 
sequently the way to know what will happen to man, each 
man, is to comprehend fully the language of numbers. 
The Pythagoreans devoted a good deal of their energies to 
this task. 

HERACLITUS took the position that the cosmic process 
is according to law. He writes: "This one order of things 
neither any one of the gods nor of men has made, but it 
always was, is, and ever shall be, an ever-living fire, kin- 
dling according to fixed measure and extinguished accord- 
ing to fixed measure." AH change, he held, is according to 
a fixed and unalterable law, a law which is the basic prin- 
ciple of the universe. Man is completely subject to this 
law. At times Heraditus speaks of this law, or principle, 
as "Fate" and at other times as "Justice * But > whatever 
name is used, the meaning is simple. At the base of the 
universe is inevitable law, to which all things, including 
man, are subject. Man has no choice but to follow the 
dictates of this law. "This alone is wise," he says, "to under- 
stand the intelligence by which all things are steered 
through all things." When man understands his fate, he 
does not rebel, but accepts it as inevitable. 



130 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

A similar point of view was taken by all the philosophers 
before Socrates. They all thought of the universe as con- 
structed by some underlying power or force, which, in 
building the universe, set its pattern so that the parts 
functioned with a complete inevitableness. Man, as part 
of this universe, was governed by this inevitableness. Al- 
though, in their philosophies, they did not make this 
inevitableness into a person with the title of Fate, never- 
theless they held to the belief that man's destiny was 
determined not by what he did but by the facts of his crea- 
tion. Thus, the Fates of popular Greek religion and the 
belief in the inevitableness of nature were the same in 
principle. 

The first break in this tradition came with the Sophists. 
They centered their attention upon man, and found in him 
unrealized possibilities. Man, "the measure of all things," 
could not be wholly bound to an inescapable process or 
law* Although they were not clear about the matter, it 
seemed impossible to them that man should not have some 
effect upon his own destiny. At least, they were certain 
that man could shape his destiny among his fellows. He 
could learn how to succeed as a member of society, to 
defend himself in the courts, and to win a position for 
himself in the state. Whatever his eternal destiny might 
be, at least he could shape his worldly existence to fit his 
desires. Man was not wholly enslaved to the Fates. 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 
This approach forced philosophers to rethink the prob- 
lem of man's relation to the universe and the forces re- 
sponsible for its existence and activity, Man would no 
longer be content to accept the inevitableness of the uni- 
verse without a challenge, without a fight, without a val- 
iant attempt to defend his own integrity. 

SOCBATES added strength to this concern with man. He 
held that man's crowning achievement is knowledge. Hav- 
ing attained knowledge, man would do the right thing, he 
would be good. Without knowledge man was in danger of 
acting wrongly. Further, he believed that man could, 



FATE VERSUS FREE WILL 131 

through biowledge, have some influence upon his destiny 
here and hereafter. Man might influence to some degree at 
least the fate which was his. Here was ths beginning of a 
belief, vague though it was, that man was possessed of 
some degree of freedom of choice. This freedom was not a 
mere sham, but upon its proper use might hinge man's 
future. 

In Socrates' thinldng, many people made wrong choices, 
and would consequently suffer. They used their freedom to 
reach evil ends. With Socrates and the Sophists we see the 
Fates loosing their grip on man. Man was rising up and 
declaring his belief in his own ability, his strength even 
against the powers of the universe. 

The belief in man's freedom is shown clearly in the writ- 
ings of PLATO. Man can and does defeat the purposes of 
the universe. Although he is a creature of the divine Crea- 
tor, he may so order his life as not to live justly and wisely. 
The appetites or the passions may gain control of him and 
refuse to obey the dictates of his highest part, reason or 
mind. The ideal is a just man with each part of his nature 
functioning in its proper way. But man can destroy this 
harmony. 

Indeed, in his later writing, the Laws, we find Plato in- 
sisting upon freedom as a necessary basis for the good life* 
He would have men free to build a life that is worth while. 
In this it is evident that Plato believes that a life that is 
good because it can be nothing else is not in reality good. 
Goodness comes because one has met evil and overcome 
it, has made a real choice and has chosen well. This im- 
plies that man is not determined by the universe, but is 
able to choose, is free to determine in the last analysis his 
own fate. 

Central in the thinking of ARISTOTLE is the belief in the 
freedom of man. Morality, for him, is not a matter of some 
inevitable law, but is a matter of free choice. He writes 
that "Virtue, as well as evil, lies in our power/' We are 
free to do that which is good or to do that which is eviL 
is no power in the universe forcing us either way. 



132 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

In another place he says, "Virtue is a disposition, or habit, 
involving deliberate purpose or choice." 

Further, Aristotle held that the supreme end of man 
was the realization of that which is highest and best in 
him as a human being, his reason. Man may choose to 
debase this or to realize it to the fullest He is free to strive 
to become all that is in him to become, or to become less. 
The ultimate choice lies within man* 

Thus, both Plato and Aristotle were certain that a world 
in which fate ruled completely could not be a good world. 
In such a world man could not be held responsible for his 
actions. Whether good or bad, he would be determined by 
a power beyond his control and could not therefore be 
blamed. Morality, in the thinking of both philosophers, 
demanded a free will, an opportunity for choice which was 
real and not a mere sham. The good man, they held, was 
one who made the right choice and through the force of 
his will realized the best. The bad man was one who made 
the wrong choice. 

Although both these philosophers recognized the exist- 
ence in the universe of certain laws and consistencies, they 
were not willing to close the universe so tightly that man's 
actions were determined in all things. They had to leave 
room for free will or freedom, lest they deny the actual 
existence of the good life. 

The Views of the Later Greek Philosophers 

The value of freedom was recognized by EPICUBUS and 
the Epicureans. However, following the atomic theory o 
Democritus, they were in danger of making such freedom 
impossible. If man, as all nature, is a result of the coming 
together of atoms and if he disappears when these atoms 
separate, then man would be subject to the nature of the 
atoms. To meet this difficulty, Epicurus held that th 
atoms were endowed with spontaneity. They were not 
pushed and pulled by forces of nature, but had the power 
to move as they willed. Thus, if man is a composition of 
atoms, he too would have the inner power to move and 
act as he willed. 



FATE VERSUS FBEE "WILL 133 

Believing that the universe of man cannot be explained 
as the result of blind fate, Epicurus was unwilling to leave 
man as the pawn of inexorable forces. Free will seemed 
important to him. As a result, he gave freedom to his atoms 
so that they might, in turn, give freedom to man. 

Thus, man can make choices, determine his fate- He 
may strive for prudence. He may seek pleasure which 
comes through the satisfaction of desires and through the 
elimination of all desire. 

ZENO and the Stoics took the other extreme position as 
regards human freedom. For them the universe is a result 
of fixed and unchanging kw. Everything in it is deter- 
mined with an absoluteness that permits no break. Even 
man's will is determined. In the entire universe there is 
nothing that can happen by chance. From the first begin- 
ning to the last end there is an unbroken chain of causes 
determined by the nature of the universe. 

Man can have no freedom of will in any true sense of 
the term, the Stoics taught Man is part of this causal chain 
and all his actions are the result of factors over which he 
can have no control 

It is possible, Zeno asserted, for man to obey graciously 
or to obey ungraciously, but in either case he must obey. 
His only freedom, then, is to accept his fate, to assent to 
what fate has decreed for him. 

According to the Stoics, everything in the universe has 
its beginning and source in the wiH of God. God is the 
ruler and the determiner. Everything which has evolved 
has been the result of God's purpose. Thus fate and God's 
will are the same. 

However, when the Stoics come to the problem of ethics 
or the good life, they abandon the complete determinism 
of their metaphysics, (By ^metaphysics" we mean the phi- 
losopher's conception of the universe and of reality.) In 
their ethics the Stoics teach that man may determine for 
himself whether or not he wifl obey the moral law, whether 
or not he will follow reason and. seek to realize the supreme 
good. Man may give himself to his passions and become 
their slave, or he may escape from his passions and rise to 



134 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

a moral life above them. As lie conquers his passions he 
becomes free. This, for the Stoic, is true freedom* 

Thus, while the Stoic, in attempting to hold to a universe 
in which cause and effect are determined, must deny free- 
dom in his metaphysics, he is unable to carry this theory to 
its logical conclusion. When he approaches the ethical 
problem he realizes that man must be free if good and bad 
are to mean anything in reality. Here the Stoic is in the 
tradition of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. 

The Position of the Greco-Religious Thinkers 

PHILO, in his attempt to reconcile Jewish religion and 
Greek philosophy, conceived of the body as the source o 
evil. When the soul comes into the body it partakes of the 
evil of the body, an evil that has been of the body fromi 
the beginning. Thus, the incarnation of the soul in the body 
is > forPhilo,afalL 

But the soul possesses what Philo thought of as pure 
intelligence, an addition which the soul receives from the 
divine, from God. This makes man akin to God, to the 
divine. However, even though the human soul is con* 
nected with the divine and is, in a sense, part of the divine, 
it has the power to freely accept or reject the rule of God* 

The divine does not exercise complete control over man, 
but makes it so that he can give himself over to sense and 
the bodily passions or conquer these and rise to the divine. 
Thus, man has a real freedom, and can exercise it to de- 
termine his own destiny in a real sense. 

Likewise, PLOTINDS conceived of the soul of man as 
part of the world soul and as thus partaking of the freedom 
of the world soul. But man's soul had the desire to shape 
and mould matter, and thus became enmeshed in matter 
and felL In this fall each soul loses its original freedom. 
As the real soul turns away from the life of sense in the 
body, it regains its freedom. The nearer it returns to God 
the more freedom it has. 

The soul, for Plotinus, has an original freedom just as 
one outside a prison has freedom. As it becomes entangled 
in matter it enters the prison house of matter and loses its 



FATE VEBSUS FREE WILL 135 

freedom. But, it can turn away from the body and regain 
its freedom. It can escape from the prison house of the 
body, of the sensual, and return to God who is perfect 
freedom. 

Whether or not each soul does this, Plotinus believed, 
rests with the soul itself. There is no compulsion on the 
part of a fate or an inescapable law, Man is free to sell his 
soul to the sensual or to free it from the body and strive 
upward to union with God* 

These early religious philosophers never doubted but 
that God was perfect freedom and, in so far as man or the 
human soul is godlike, it partakes of this freedom. Thus, 
for them, man is fundamentally free. But, because of their 
almost universal contempt for the world as the seat of evil, 
they believed that the incarnation of this free soul in a body 
or in matter was a fall and a loss of freedom. However, in 
this incarnation the soul did not lose its ability to rescue 
itself. It was still free to become free from the body if it so 
willed. All of these thinkers were unwilling to give matter 
absolute power over the souL 

Early and Medieval Christian Thinkers 

This conception was carried over into early Christianity. 
The Apologists without exception taught that man is bas- 
ically free and that he has fallen through his contact with 
body. At the creation, they believed, the soul was endowed 
with the ability to choose between the good and the eviL 
As a result, some souls chose to turn from God and give 
themselves over to the sins of matter. But man is able, 
through the aid of the divine and the living of a Christian 
life, to return to God. Man can make a choice which will 
determine forever his destiny. This choice is real and eter- 
nal. Thus, the freedom of man is real in that it enables him 
to determine his estate forever. 

The early Christian doctrine of the work of Jesus is in 
line with this theory. Jesus, the Apologists believed, came 
to save man from sin. But sin implies guilt on the part of 
man and guilt is meaningless unless man is in some way 
responsible for his sin* You cannot hold a man as guilty of 



136 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

an act unless he is able to act differently. Thus, only if man 
is free to choose can he be condemned for his sin. If man 
has sinned, he must be free* 

Further, the early Christians argued that God, who is 
aH good and perfect, cannot be responsible for evil and six* 
in the world. Thus, man must shoulder tins responsibility* 
and must be free. The early Christian monk PELAGIUS 
taught that God had given freedom to man so that he may 
make a choice between good and evfl. Each man makes 
his own choice, but he retains his freedom of choice. Thus, 
he may turn away from sin by an act of his free will, re* 
pudiate evil, and receive divine forgiveness. 

It is obvious, then, that freedom was believed by these 
early Christians to be necessary to account for the work 
of Jesus and the whole scheme of salvation, 

The conception of individual freedom was denied by 
SAINT AUGUSTINE. According to hi, mankind was free in 
Adam, but since Adam chose to sin, he lost freedom not 
only for himself but for all men and for all time. Now no 
one is free, but all are bound to sin, are slaves of evil* 

But God makes a choice among men of those whom he 
wiH save and those whom he will permit to be destroyed 
because of sin. This choice is not influenced by any act of 
an individual man, but is determined only by what God 
wants. 

In Augustine we find both fatalism and .predestination; 
as far as the individual man is concerned. With Adam 
there was no fatalism. He was free. But God knew even 
then how Adam would act, knew that he would sin. Thus,, 
from the beginning God made up his mind whom he 
would save* These were predestined from the first to sal- 
vation, and alt the rest were predestined to eternal punish- 
ment. Adam's sin, for Augustine, became hereditary, with 
the result that the future of every man is completely de- 
termined and has been so from the beginning of time. 

The doctrine of original sin, so prevalent in the early 
Christian church, led in Augustine to a belief in fatalism 
as far as the individual man is concerned. His future is 



FATE YEBSUS FREE WELZ. 137 

sealed not by any act of his, but by the act of the first man 
and the free will of God himself . 

ABELABD was not in complete agreement with Saint 
Augustine, but held that aT* is actually free to choose 
between good and evfl. Sin, for him, consisted in the con- 
senting to do an evil act which is recognized by the indi- 
vidual as evil If one does wrong,but intends to do right, 
he is not a sinner. But, if he knows that an act is wrong 
and persists in doing it, he is sinning. This choice of act is 
a matter of the free wffl of man. He can actually decide 
on the basis of his lenowledge and can act in terms of his 
decision. 

While Augustine took from man aH choice, Abelard gave 
choice back to man in order to preserve the fact of guilt 
and sin. Without choice sin could not exist, he held. 

With THOMAS AQTJINAS we find a dear belief in the free- 
dom of the human wOL Man, he taught, is a being with a 
wiH and with intelligence. He is not pushed from without 
like the animals, but can determine his actions. His will 
may follow his intellect doing what the intellect says is 
right. But the wffl can choose to act or not to act When 
his reason tells hfrm that a certain course of action is good, 
man can decide which particular acts are best suited to 
the realization of the end proposed. 

However, when Thomas Aquinas turns to a considera- 
tion of specific religious doctrines, he modifies his doctrine 
of free will somewhat He believed, as did Augustine, in 
the doctrine of original sin. Adam's sin, for htm, was trans* 
mitted to all men, and carried with it the natural conse- 
quences of sin. Only divine grace can bring salvation* But, 
even where God wishes to bestow this salvation, the hu- 
man will must co-operate. God foresees that some will not 
accept the offer of grace, and predestines them to eternal 
punishment. 

JOHN DUNS Scorns taugiht that if the human wffl were 
inferior to the human intellect, as Aquinas had believed, it 
could not be free. If the will had to look to the intellect for 
direction, it would be subject to the intellect. Therefore, to 



138 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT MODLOSOPHEBS 

make the will wholly free, he taught that it was superior to 
the intellect. 

The will, then, for Scotus is completely free and can 
inake decisions between sense and the moral law. The will 
is the highest facility of the soul, higher than intellect 
This leads, of course, to the position that the will is the 
final determiner of right and wrong. What the will deter- 
mines as good is good simply because the will has said 
that ft is good 

Carried over to the idea of God, this doctrine leads one 
to the position that God's will is superior to his intellect, 
and that right is right simply because God wills it to be 
right and not because it is right in terms of reason. God 
has made certain things right. He could just as well have 
made the opposite things right since it is his arbitrary will 
which determines the right The will of God is arbitrary. 

This is the extreme of the position that the will is free. 
As long as will is influenced in its action by the intellect or 
reason, it cannot be wholly free. But^ if it is free also of 
reason, it has reached the peak of freedom. This is the 
direction of Scotus* thinking, although he tends to draw 
bade from the final logical results of his position, complete 
chaos since every human will would become a law unto 
itself. That which I will is right, and that which you will 
is right There can be no measure above the human will, 
Scotus drew back when he found himself approaching 
this conclusion. But he held tenaciously to the idea that 
the human will is free and is not subject to the intellect 
Indeed, he took the position that if it was necessary for 
him to have either intellect without will or will without in- 
tellect, he would choose the latter. He was, in this, one of 
the great champions of the freedom of the will. 

With the Renaissance, man undertook to free himself 
from the dominance of the Church and its doctrines and 
to study the world freely. This was an assertion in fact of 
man's freedom. The human mind refused longer to be tied 
to the doctrines and beliefs of the past, but aspired to 
search the universe with unblinded eyes and tell what it 
found there. 



FATE VEHStTS FREE WHJL 139 

It is a curious fact, however, that as man undertook 
this search he began to discover inexorable laws and math- 
ematical consistencies by which everything in the universe 
seemed to bd controlled. The early scientists turned from 
the Church and from Aristotle to the world round about 
There they found things happening in what appeared to 
them mechanical ways. Galileo, Kepler, Sir Isaac Newton, 
each found the events of the universe following what ap- 
peared to be definite laws. 

And into this system of laws man seemed to fit of ne- 
cessity. His being, his actions, even his thoughts were con- 
ceived to be subject to the laws of the universe, laws 
which brooked no interference or change. Thus, man was 
freed from the authority of the past and of the Church to 
find himself again in bondage to a master more powerful 
and unyielding than any he had known before. He became, 
in the philosophies of many of the Renaissance scientists, 
merely a part of a mechanical universe controlled by forces 
in the universe and of no meaning save as a unit in the 
inexorable whole. 

The Views of Bacon, Holibes, Descartes, and Spinoza 

FRANCIS BACON is typical of man's earnest desire to be 
free from the traditions of the past and to approach the 
universe without religious or intellectual bias. Fundamental 
to his thinking was the belief that man must free himself 
from the forms and prejudices of the past and follow a 
new method in studying the universe. His aim was to free 
the mind from the "idols" which the past has foisted upon 
it so that it might consider its universe clearly. 

Then, having been freed, the human mind will, he was 
certain, be able to discover the laws which govern the 
universe and determine its every action. 

Nevertheless, Bacon was not wholly able to escape the 
notions of the past. Although he relegated religion to a 
realm of its own outside of and different from philosophy, 
he held that there were religious laws which man must 
obey whether they appeared to be reasonable or not. By 
separating theology and philosophy, Bacon was able to 



14O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

free philosophy so that it might undertake an unbiased 
study of the universe. But he left man subject to the will 
of God and thereby shorn of his freedom. It is obvious 
that this condition ccmld not long satisfy the thinking mind. 
It was far too contradictory. 

THOMAS HOBBES saw the unsatisfactory results of the 
position suggested by Bacon, and went a step further by 
holding that all in the universe was subject to a purely 
mechanical series of cause and effect Everything, even the 
actions and destiny of man, he argued, can be explained 
mechanically. All the universe is motion. All thoughts or 
ideas are simply motions in the brain. 

Thus, for Hobbes, to hold that man is a free will is ab- 
surd. An individual finds himself the scene of alternating 
desires and aversions. He wants to do some things and does 
not want to do others. As these opposites pky across his 
mind, he is deliberating, thinking. The last desire or aver- 
sion is called will. He completes his deliberation and de- 
cides to act or not to act. 

Each desire or aversion is caused. Consequently the last 
desire or aversion, the point at which one stops, is also 
caused. Thus, the will is caused and cannot be free. A 
man is, Hobbes held, free to act after he has willed, but 
is not free to will or not to will. The very nature of his 
being makes him a willing being. He must will. But he 
can choose to act or not to act on the willing which he 
does. 

The problem of DESCARTES was, as we have seen, to 
reconcile the mechanical theories of his time with the ideas 
of God, soul, and freedom. He was not contented to ac- 
cept the mechanistic view of the universe, including man, 
which the science of his day seemed to demand. At the 
same time, he was unwilling to discredit science altogether 
and return to the older spiritualistic tradition. 

His solution lay in making a sharp distinction between 
mind and body. The body, for him, was part of the or- 
ganic universe and was governed by purely mechanical 
processes. He believed that here cause and effect was 
supreme, that there were no breaks in the chain of causes, 



FATE VERSUS FREE WHX 

and that everything was determined by what went before. 
All the universe, including man, could therefore be ex- 
plained mechanically. 

The mind, or soul, however, is free. It wills an active 
principle. It is free, for example, to will to love God or not 
It is free to think pure thoughts or not It is free to create 
imaginary pictures and to move the body in any way it 
cares. The volitional part of man's nature, then, is in the 
soul, and can be influenced by the body only indirectly. 

The will, according to Descartes, is independent of the 
body, and can, if it so desires, produce states of the body. 
The will is free. Further, the ideal for which man should 
strive is to keep the will free from influences of the body 
and any other outside influences. 

While Descartes had separated inind and body in an 
effort to reconcile the mechanistic science of his day and 
the religion of the times, he left unanswered the question 
of the relationship between mind and body. How can the 
free will of the individual influence the body? This was 
the problem which his immediate successors attacked. 

The Occasionalists, of whom GTTEIJNCX is a representa- 
tive, held that God is aware at aH times of what an in- 
dividual is going to will, and he arranges the universe so 
that the thing which I will happens. The human will is 
free, but God has foreknowledge and thus can act so that 
it looks as though the will was influencing the body or 
other bodies. 

Other successors of Descartes, BLAISE PASCAL and 
PIERBE BAYLE for example, placed freedom in the realm 
of religion and held that though we cannot prove man's 
freedom by reasoning, we can know that man is free 
through a direct religious experience. 

In SPINOZA we find a complete abandoning of the idea 
of freedom. His philosophic system is absolutely determin- 
istic. Everything in the universe follows from something 
else in a definite causal chain each link of which is neces- 
sarily connected with the one preceding and the one 
following. 

God, or Substance, for Spinoza, is absolutely independ* 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

ent, self-caused and self-determined. God is wholly and 
completely free. However, all finite objects and all thoughts 
form two lines each interconnected in strict causal se- 
quence. Thus, while the underlying substance of all things 
and all thoughts is free, the individual thing or thought 
cannot be free but is determined by its history, its past. 
Thus, there cannot be any such thing as a free will. The 
will, for Spinoza, is simply the soul affirming or denying 
what is true and false. The intellect and the will are es- 
sentially the same. The will is nothing more than an idea 
which one might have affirming or denying itself. And the 
affirmation is determined by the idea. Consequently the 
will is under the dominance of the intellect and cannot 
in any sense be free. 

Further, the will can have no effect on the body. Both 
body and mind are attributes of God or Substance, and 
each is independent of the other. 

Man, Spinoza holds, is fooled into thinking he is free be- 
cause he does not see the chain of causes which determine 
his action. Indeed, any object equally ignorant might think 
that it was free. But when man comes to understand the 
causal chain, he realizes that he is in no way free. 

Spinoza also teaches that we have different stages of the 
wiH. At one level are the passions. These are confused and 
inadequate ideas. Here we will before the idea is complete 
and definite. Adequate ideas result in will proper, the ade- 
quate action upon ideas. As man attains to these adequate 
ideas he is freed from his passions and acts in the light of 
clear understanding. When a man knows, he is free from 
hate, fear, anger and the like. But his will is always de- 
termined by his understanding and therefore cannot be 
thought of as free. 

The Position of Locke, of Hume, and of Leibnitz 

To ask whether a man's will is free or not is, according 
to JOHN LOCKE, a foolish question. "It is as insignificant/* 
he writes, "to ask whether a man's will be free as to ask 
whether his sleep be swift or his virtue square." This is 
true, he argues, because the will is the power of an in- 



FATE VEBSUS FEEE "WHX 143 

dividual to think his own actions and to prefer their 
doing or not doing. If one is able to think about his actions 
and is able to prefer one action over and above another, 
he has will. On the other hand, freedom is also a power, 
the power to do or not to do any particular thing in terms 
of what he wills. 

Man may have both powers. He may be able to think 
clearly about his actions and reach a preference among 
possible actions. Further, he may be able to do that which 
he prefers or he may find himself unable to act in accord 
with his preference. But these are two powers and must 
be recognized as such, Locke urges. 

God, Locke holds, has endowed man with certain desires 
or uneasinesses of the mind for want of some absent good. 
These desires determine the will. The individual deter- 
mines to do that which is most pressing. He sets about to 
realize the desire which is paramount. This he wills to do. 

DAVID HUME held that the idea of necessity and the idea 
of cause which men have are the result of observation of 
the uniformity in nature. As men see the world about them, 
they recognize that certain things always follow other 
things. This leads them to reason that there is a necessary 
causal connection between the two things. 

Likewise, as men watch themselves they discover that 
when they desire something, actions follow which are di- 
rected toward securing that something. 

Thus, because of these experiences, men move to the 
conclusion that the universe is characterized by causal ne^ 
cessity and that there is a relation of cause and effect 
between a man's desires and the actions in which he en- 
gages. However, men find a necessity in the causal rela- 
tionships of nature but do not find a similar necessity when 
they study their own actions. While they believe that na- 
ture is characterized by a rigid cause and effect relation- 
ship, their own actions are not so rigidly determined by 
their motives. 

But, wherever there is uniformity of action, Hume holds, 
there is necessity. There is uniformity in nature and there is 
a like uniformity in man's actions. Consequently, we can 



144 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT 3PHJLOSOPHEBS 

inf er from one act to its cause just as we can infer from one 
thing in nature to its cause. Man's actions result from his 
character and are necessary results of that character. Give 
him another character, and his actions wffl be different 
Freedom, for Hume, is merely this necessary connection* 
So long as man's actions arise from his own character, na- 
ture, or desires, they are free. If, however, he acts be- 
cause of some external compulsion contrary to his char- 
acter of desires, he is not free. 

For example, a man strikes another. If this action is a 
result of his inner nature, his character or desire, it is 
brought about necessarily from the nature which is his, 
but he is free in so acting. However, if someone else forces 
him to strike the individual against his own desire and 
character, he is not free. In both instances there is neces- 
sity. But, in the first case the necessity is that of the very 
nature of the man acting, while, in the second case, tibe 
necessity comes from without him and is not in accord with 
his nature. 

GOTTFRIED WDLHELM: LEIBNTTZ tackled the same prob- 
lem as did Descartes. He realized that, in some way, phi- 
losophy must reconcile the achievements of science and the 
elements of Christianity which were considered valuable. 
But, while Descartes conceived of one universal substance 
and two attributes, Leibnitz believed in the existence of an 
infinite number of minute units or substances, the monads. 
^ Each monad, he held, is completely insulated from any 
influences outside of itself. It cannot be determined by any- 
toing other than that which it is. It "has no windows." 
lUerefore, whatever it does is a result of its own nature 
and not because of forces outside it. 

Man, like all objects in nature, is composed of a number 
of monads intricately organized. Since each monad is in- 
flated from without and is thereby free from outside in- 
fluences, so man must be free from such influences. How- 
ever, just as the monad is determined from within by the 
TT, ? ?** ***** nature > so man fe determined from 
w?/ r y OWn mture ' ** own ^Prises and desires. 
Will, for Leibnitz, is simply the conscious striving of an 



FATE VERSUS FBEE WILI, 145 

individual, striving that is guided by a clear idea. Man 
knows what he wants, and strives to attain it This striving 
is his will. Thus, will is always determined by the idea 
which the individual has of what he wants. Choice is sim- 
ply the selecting of the desire that is strongest Man is 
never free, in any absolute sense of the term, to decide 
for one action or for another regardless of his desires. He 
must decide for the desire which is strongest, and must 
strive to realize it through his actions. We will what our 
nature tells us is best 

Leibnitz believed that in this theory he had saved man 
from the mechanism of science and made possible the reali- 
zation of the values of Christian thought The monad was 
not open to influence from the outside and therefore not 
mechanically determined. Its actions were determined by 
its own inner nature, and thus were free. 

Fate and Free WiU According ta Voltaire and to Rousseau 

In his earlier writings the great French propagandist of 
the movement in philosophy foaown as the Enlightenment, 
VOLTAIRE, taught a doctrine of the freedom of the will that 
bordered on complete irresponsibility, but in his later works 
we find him abandoning frfc for an almost equally com- 
plete determinism. He wrote, "When I can do what I wiH, 
I am free; but I will necessarily what I will* 

There followed a long list of brilliant thinkers who, in- 
fluenced more by the scientific side of the philosophies of 
their predecessors, sought to prove that man was wholly 
and completely a machine devoid of anything which might 
in any sense be called freedom of the wilL They saw man 
in all his parts a being similar to the intricate machines 
which inventors were constructing. JOHN TOLAND, DAVID 
HARTLEY, JOSEPH PBIESTLEY, LA METIBIE, BARON D*HOL- 
BACH, and many others taught that thought is merely a 
function of the brain and that the human individual is 
wholly and completely determined by the play of forces in 
the universe so that he is tossed here and there as these 
forces meet and separate. He has nothing that could be 



146 BASIC TEACB3NGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

called a will which might have power to shape these forces 
to ends which might be his. 

The general position of all the Enlightenment philoso- 
phers was that man in all aspects is governed by the same 
laws which govern the natural world. For them man was 
just another, but more intricate and amusing, machine. 

A bomb was dropped into the midst of this brilliant 
group of thinkers by JEAN JACQUES ROUSSEAU. He took is- 
sue with the basic positions of all these men when he af- 
firmed that the truest characteristic of man was not the 
scientific mind but the feeling heart. Man, for him, is not 
a toy in the hands of natural laws, but is a free soul striving 
to live according to the dictates of this freedom. Rousseau 
saw in this trend toward the sciences the inevitable destruc- 
tion of aH that man had come to believe was of most value. 
Thus, he threw himself against this flood and sought to 
stem the tide which threatened to engulf mankind. 

Kant> Fichte, Schelling, Schopenhauer, and 
Other German Thinkers 

It is said that when KANT received his copy of Rous- 
seau's Emile he was so fascinated by the arguments there 
developed and the point of view taken that he neglected to 
take his afternoon walk. To so neglect was almost a major 
tragedy in the community since the old philosopher was so 
prompt each day that villagers could set their watches by 
his appearance at his door. It was Rousseau who stimu- 
lated Kant to his great attempt to save man's freedom in a 
world of science. 

Kant took the position that, so long as one sticks to ex- 
perience, there is no proof of freedom. In experience we 
find necessary connections, cause and effect Thus, we are 
not able to prove theoretically the existence of free will. So 
far Kant was in agreement with the mechanists, those who 
saw the world as an interlocking series of mechanical laws 
and their operations. From the point of view of pure rea- 
son there is no evidence to support a belief in free will. 
But, Kant believed that the mind had the faculty of 
Reason, a faculty engaged in bringing together the various 



FATE VERSUS FBEE "WILL 147 

processes, events, or occurrences into wholes or Ideas. 
These Ideas, though not matters of experience, are legiti- 
mate bases for man's reasoning. And, the results of such 
reasoning are to be accepted as legitimate bases for beliefs 
and actions. 

The Idea of freedom is not to be found in experience. 
Here we find only cause and effect ad fafinttum, on and on 
as far as we can go. But, Kant argues, ft is legitimate for 
us to go beyond experience to "transcendental ideas," ideas 
created by Reason independently of experience. 

Further, to preserve the moral life, it is necessary for 
man to believe in freedom. This is a practical idea, a nec- 
essary belief. Freedom of the will, then, is an idea which 
man erects because of the demands of his moral nature. It 
is necessary, and thus legitimate, even though it cannot 
be proved by experience. 

Man, then, for Kant, is a free agent. He is capable of 
acting voluntarily so that his acts are not links in a chain of 
natural causes. Man, a free agent, originates the act which, 
when seen by the mind, is part of an intricate web of 
cause and effect. 

It is impossible, Kant held, ever to prove that the will is 
free. Nevertheless, because such a belief is necessary, we 
can act and live as if the will was free. When we so act 
and live, we discover that certain moral insights are possi- 
ble. For example, we are then able to hold each individual 
responsible for his actions, and we are in a position to strive 
for a better life. We are not drowned in complete moral 
despair, not caught in the inevitable tangle of cause and 
effect which characterizes the world of nature. Life be- 
comes meaningful for us as human beings when we can be- 
lieve that what we do is the result of free choice, and has, 
thereby, a moral meaning. The moral consciousness of man 
implies that the will is free. 

Kant, in this position, makes a place for the values which 
the science of his day was fast pushing out of the picture. 
He agreed with the scientists that experience left no room 
for these values. But, they were so necessary that we are 
justified in acting as though they were reaL 



148 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Basic to this position was the thesis that there is a higher 
truth than that of the sciences, the truth of the moral na- 
ture of man* The moral law within man is a guarantee of 
the world beyond the senses, a world in which freedom 
applies. Faith in this world was Kant's way of escape from 
the deadening world of experience. 

FICHTE began his thinking at this point. Fundamental to 
Fichte's point of view was the belief fa freedom, the idea 
that the will, or as he called it *the ego" (meaning the 
*T), is not a link in the scientific chain of cause and effect, 
but is free, self-determining activity. This will is, for him, 
the only real thing in the universe. 

The ego, being pure activity, creates the world which it 
knows. My world is not something given to me from the 
outside, but is a creation of the pure, active, free ego, of 
which I am a part. The Absolute ego, or God, is free and 
sdf-determined Each individual ego, or will, is a part of 
this Absolute ego and is likewise free and creative. What 
I do, as an individual, is simply the Absolute ego acting, 
and, as it is free, so am I free. 

If, some will ask, what I do is merely the realization of 
the purposes of the Absolute ego, am I not a slave of this 
ego? Fichte's answer was to the effect that we can decide 
whether we will be blind tools of this Absolute ego or will 
be conscious, willing instruments of its purpose. In making 
this choice we, as individuals, are free. But, having made 
the choice, we are no longer free. My freedom lies, then, 
in my choice as to whether I will willingly or unwillingly 
serve the Absolute ego. It is freedom of choice. 

SCHF.T.T.TNG took very much the same view as Fichte. For 
him, likewise, the ground of the universe was a creative, 
free, living ego or principle of which everything is an ex- 
pression. As man sets up his idea freedom, he reads free- 
dom into the universe and comes to know the Absolute ego 
as a principle of freedom. As we live a life of creative 
freedom, he held, we realize that the universe is at heart 
free. "Freedom,* he writes, "can be comprehended only 
by freedom/* 
In the philosophy of SCHLEIERMACHER an attempt is 



FATE VERSUS FBEE WILL, 149 

made to salvage human freedom from the doctrine of the 
Absolute. Here the individual egos are thought of as in the 
Absolute. They are parts of the universe, and, thus, are 
controlled by the universe as a whole. They must fit into 
the universe, conform to its laws and requirements. How- 
ever, each individual is endowed with its own special and 
particular abilities or talents. If these are not allowed to 
develop and reach full bloom, the universe will not develop 
to its fullest. Therefore, the individual is free to develop 
itself, to grow in terms of its inner nature or talents. 

Schleiermacher, because of bis basic theory of the de- 
pendence of the individual upon the "world-ground" or 
Absolute, was in grave danger of so merging the individual 
with this Absolute as to leave him wholly determined by 
the laws of the Absolute. He saved himself from this com- 
plete determinism by putting emphasis upon the specific 
contribution which each ego must make to the develop- 
ment of the whole if the Absolute is to realize itself fully. 

HEGEL held that the universe is a process of evolution in. 
which that which was inherent at the beginning is finally 
realized. In this realization the whole becomes itself to the 
fullest. The rose, for example, is inherent in the seed, and is 
the result of the process of evolution from seed to rose. 
However, the seed is not fully itself until the rose has 
bloomed. This is true of the universe, Hegel believed. 

Since God is, for Hegel, the living, moving reason of the 
world, he becomes fully conscious and the universe be- 
comes fully realized only in the minds of human beings. 
The self-conscious individual is the fullest realization of the 
universe. 

But this individual must be free. Freedom is inherent in 
the universe from the beginning and is realized fully in a 
human being in a society which makes for freedom. Prog- 
ress, for Hegel, is the development of the consciousness of 
freedom. 

Hegel saw freedom as the end and goal of his dialectical 
process, a process of development from the simplest and 
most primitive to the Absolute Mind. Man is free, but he is 
free to realize the nature of the universe. In realizing this 



15O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

nature, lie is realizing himself. Therefore, man is free to 
realize himself to the fullest, 

HEBBAOT refused to follow the lead of Fichte, Schelling, 
and Hegel in defending the doctrine of freedom. He could 
see no freedom for man. His ambition was to build a 
science of the human mind which would be parallel to the 
physical sciences. In endeavoring to do this, he believed 
that he had found certain definite laws of human behavior 
which were so absolute as to allow no freedom on the part 
of the individual Everything, he argued, follows fixed laws, 
the laws of a definite science. 

On the other hand SCHOPENHAUER taught that the heart 
of the universe is wflL Striving or will is to be found in, 
everything, the principle of its existence. As we move 
from the rock, for example, to man, we see will becoming 
conscious of itself. Will is constant, persistent, eternal in 
everything. 

This will to live, will to be, is the cause of all struggle, 
suffering, and evil in the world. la such a world, to be 
moral is to have pity for others. Sympathy prompts good 
acts. But, if man can evidence sympathy and remorse, his 
will must be free. Indeed, he is free to negate his will. 

Schopenhauer sees man's will as the basis of all evil, in 
that it makes man selfish. He wills what he wills and thus 
is self-centered. But he is also able to show sympathy, to 
suffer remorse for his deeds and those of others. In this he 
denies his wilL Man is happy and at peace when, and only 
when, he has suppressed his selfish desires, when he has 
denied, negated his will, when he wills not to will. 

The Position of MM and of Green 

JOHN STUART MTT,T. agrees with the views of Hume when 
he asserts that all the confusion in modern thought as re- 
gards the problem of free will is due to a misunderstanding 
of terms. It is true, he points out, that human actions are 
the result of many factors. There is a sequence of events 
which, if wholly known, will enable one to predict the fu- 
ture acts of an individual. 

One of these causes or factors is the desire of the indi- 
vidual. It is possible for me to resist other factors, to desire 



FATE VEBSUS FREE WILL Igl 

something to be different and to work toward that end. 
This fact makes possible a sense of moral freedom. Without 
this ability to desire, and the power of desire in shaping re- 
sults, it would not be possible for us to hold our fellows 
guilty of their sins. A fully deterministic universe has no 
place for praise or blame. But, Mill sees the basis for praise 
and blame in the fact that one of the causes of an act is the 
desire of the individual. 

Freedom, then, is a fact of human existence, according 
to Mill. 

THOMAS HELL GBEEN saw that past experiences deter- 
mined the factors which an individual accepted as good 
and those he accepted as evil. But, even in these past ex- 
periences, man has been a factor, and has, thus, had a part 
in determining his experiences. Therefore, he is responsible 
for the kind of good which appeals to him now. 

Further, Green finds man able to think of a better land 
of world. He is able to build ideals of and for himself, 
visions of what he may strive to become. Indeed, having 
constructed these ideals, man is able to strive to realize 
them, strive to be better in the future. Therefore, Green 
argued, man is free, free to will a better existence. 

This ability to will, to strive, and in some degree to ac- 
complish, makes man a moral agent and responsible for his 
acts. Man is free, therefore he must accept responsibility 
for his deeds. 

The Views of James and Dewey 

WILLIAM JAMES found in man a will to believe, and 
this he put at the base of his thinking. Every system of 
philosophy, he argued, depends in the last analysis upon 
the will to believe. Man wants to believe in a certain way, 
because the belief seems to satisfy him most completely. 
This is the pragmatic test. It fits and works. 

Now, if the will to believe is so fundamental, man cannot 
be bound down by immutable laws and conditions. He 
must be a part of the picture in a real sense. Thus, he 
must be free. Man, in this world, is free to build his ideals 
and to risk all on their realization. 

JOHN DEWEY goes even further. He conceives of a world 



152 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

which, is in the making, and man as doing some o the 
creating. Unless this is all a sham, a play before an audi- 
ence, man must be free to make decisions and to have his 
decisions count in the ultimate nature of things. Human 
wants, desires, willings are determiners of the universe. 

Though, subject to the factors of the universe in which 
man lives, he is able to inquire, think, plan, reach decisions 
and act upon them with the result that the universe is 
changed by his action. For Dewey, the pivot of progress 
is the intelligent human being freely foreseeing the possi- 
ble consequences of events and throwing himself into the 
stream in order to, in a degree at least, change the course 
of the stream so that it conforms more fully to has ideals. 

Thus, throughout the history of human thought man 
has struggled with the question: Am I a mere pawn on the 
chessboard of universal forces over which I can have no 
control, or am I able to determine my fate, my destiny, to 
some degree at least? Philosophers have taken both sides of 
this issue, and many have ranged themselves between the 
two extremes. By far the great majority of philosophers 
have endeavored to find some freedom for man. Neverthe- 
less, there have been many who have more or less willingly 
turned man over to some inscrutable fate. But, the human 
mind cannot long be content to place itself wholly in the 
hands of fate. It inevitably rises up to proclaim its freedom 
and challenge whatever forces there be to beat it down. 

Inevitably death must overtake man. The pessimists 
stand up to assert that death has proven their point, and 
that man, no matter how he may protest, is at last forced 
to bow to a fate which he can no longer challenge. But the 
optimists will answer back that death is no defeat, but is 
actually a victory for the will of man. 

Though beaten down time and again by forces in the 
universe, man rises up again and again to proclaim 

I am the master of my -fate, 
1 am the captain of my soul. 



Chapter VI 
THE SOUL AND IMMORTALITY 

EMPEDOCLES PLATO ARISTOTLE PLOTTNUS 

AUGUSTINE AQUINAS BRUNO 

DESCARTES SPINOZA LOCKE LEIBNITZ 

KANT SCHLEIERMACHER SCHOPENHAUER 

LOTZE COMTE JAMES BEWEY 



Is death the end of human existence? Or is there more 
for man in a land beyond the grave? Can we find in 
man a soul, something distinct from his body, which 
can survive the event of death and live eternally? 
What can we believe about heaven and hell? 



Death is a universal experience. All men, whether great 
or small, wealthy or poor, high or low, must inevitably 
move toward that hour when life will cease and the body 
return to the dust from which it came. To the eye, this is 
the end, the finale, the conclusion- The body, if left to it- 
self, will disintegrate and disappear, so that, in time, every 
trace of its existence will be gone. 

And so it has been since Efe first appeared on this earth. 
Living is but a short span and is soon done with. Death 
writes "Finis" to life, and the living of yesterday is soon for- 
gotten. Man is born, grows, struggles, dreams, plans, and 
builds, only to surrender at last to death. 

But the human mind has never been content to let the 
matter rest here. Throughout the history of mankind there 
has persisted a conviction, sometimes dim and at other 



154 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

times very vivid, that death cannot be the end, that the 
grave is not a victory of man's foes, that death does not 
inflict a cosmic sting. In every age there have been mil- 
lions firm in the belief that what is truest in humanity per- 
sists in some form or state after death. 

Early man had his dreams. In these he roamed far and 
wide, hunted and fished, and had many adventures and 
endured many perils. But, when he awoke his friends as- 
sured him that he had not moved from his cave or tent. 
Since this happened so often, he came to believe that there 
was something about him which could free itself from the 
body and live its own life. This was probably the begin- 
ning of a belief in the human soul. 

But, if man had this soul, other things must also have 
souls. The early men believed, as we have pointed out, that 
all nature was alive. The tree had a soul or spirit; the river 
had a soul; and everything else in primitive man's universe 
had a soul, a spirit which could leave the body and return 
to it after going where it would and doing what it cared. 

It was a very early belief that what affected the body 
had little or no effect upon the soul. The freedom which 
the soul enjoyed to come and go and the special nature of 
the soul made it immune*, more or less, to the happenings 
of the body. Thus, it was but natural that man should be- 
lieve that the soul survived the body and continued to be 
active long after the body had been lost. 

In this way mankind gradually built up the belief in the 
human soul as something distinct from the body, and in the 
immortality of this soul, the existence of the soul after death 
had destroyed the body. 

But, for many early peoples this immortality of the soul 
was not necessarily eternal. Having left the body, the soul, 
some believed, remained near by for some time, returning 
to the place of the body at intervals. Therefore, food, 
drink, and other necessities were placed with the body so 
that the soul migiht be cared for. 

Other peoples believed that the soul left one body only 
to take up its abode in another body. Here we find the idea 
that the former life of the soul determined what kind of a 



THE SOUL AND IMMORTALITY 155 

body it entered. A good soul entered a better body or one 
higher in the scale, while a bad soul had to enter a body 
farther down the scale. 

Still others believed that the soul went to a place of 
shades and ghostly forms, there to pine for the world of 
men. The early Greelcs and the ancient Hebrews, among 
others, held to such a belief. Their dead spent eternity in a 
dark, uninviting, and cheerless region in misery and re- 
morse. 

The Soul as Viewed by the Early Greek Philosophers 

Most of the early Greek thinkers built their theories of 
the soul and of immortality upon the popular beliefs which 
were native to the culture in which they lived. That all 
nature was alive, few questioned. Nor did they question the 
belief that man had a soul which was, in some way, the 
real part of him. The earliest Greek philosophers thought 
of this soul, as the least material form of the particular 
substance out of which everything in the universe was 
made. 

For example, ANAXIMENES, who taught that the under- 
lying substance of the universe was air, likewise held that 
the soul was very thin or rarefied air and that this sub- 
stance was the thing which held the individual together. 
When it left the body disintegration set in and the body 
was destroyed. 

PYTHAGORAS, and his followers, the Pythagoreans, held 
that the destiny of the soul after leaving the body was 
determined by die life in the body. Consequently, they 
prepared long and involved rules which each man should 
know and follow with the utmost severity in order to in- 
sure a desirable existence after death. 

In the teachings of HERACLXTCTS we find the belief that 
the vital principle of the universe is the ever-living fire. 
This is, also, the principle of life or soul of the individual 
human being. The soul is the finest (most rarefied) form 
of fire, ever-changing, but never being destroyed. To this 
basic belief, Heraditus added the idea that souls varied in 
quality. Some souls are very dry and warm. These are the 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

best souls since they are most like the great cosmic soul, 
the soul of the universe, the purest fire. Other souls are not 
so dry and not so warm. They are less like the cosmic fire 
and, thus, are less good. 

Souls, according to EMPEDOCLES, leave one body at its 
death only to enter another body and continue to live. 
This is known as the doctrine of the transmigration of souls. 
Instead of leaving the body and going to some place re- 
served for souls, or instead of being destroyed with the 
body, this doctrine holds that the soul migrates, moves on, 
from one body to another when its present abode is no 
longer habitable. This belief was general among members 
of a famous early religious group, the Orphics, who influ- 
enced many of the early thinkers and had a wide following 
during the pre-Christian and early Christian eras. 

LEUCEPPUS, DEMOCRTTUS, and the other Atomists, taught 
that, just as the entire world is composed of atoms, or very 
tiny bits of matter, so the soul is composed of the finest, 
purest, most perfect fire atoms. These atoms are, they held, 
scattered throughout the body, a soul atom placed be- 
tween two other atoms. While man lives, he breathes soul 
atoms in and out When he dies, the soul atoms are scat- 
tered throughout the universe. The body is likened to a jar 
in which are many soul atoms. When the jar is broken at 
death, the soul atoms are spilled out. 

But these atoms are not lost or destroyed. Indeed, for 
these philosophers, the destruction of atoms is impossible. 
Soul atoms may be scattered, but they enter into other 
bodies, rearranging themselves and thus creating another 
being. Change, these men believed, is not absolute. We 
cannot create or destroy in any real sense of the term. 
Actually the only change possible is that of reassembling 
of atoms into new patterns or beings. Soul atoms live for- 
ever, but are constantly being rearranged in the universe 
just as are all other atoms. 

Democritus taught, as did some of the early Atomists, 
that the soul is to be identified with reason, the thinking 
and j'udging part of man. 



THE SOT7I, AND EMCMORTAUIT 157 

The Soul and Immortality According to 
Plato and Aristotle 

PLATO distinguishes between the soul of the world and 
individual souls of human beings. In his book, the Timaeus, 
he describes, in somewhat mythological terms, how the 
Demiurge, or world architect, endowed the world with a 
soul, the cause of motion, beauty, order and harmony. This 
world soul is between the world of ideas and the world of 
things which we see and experience. It acts according to 
definite laws, the laws of its own nature, and is the cause 
of aU law, harmony, order, o life, mind, and knowledge. 
This Demiurge also created, according to Plato, souls of 
aU the planets and all individual souls. These individual 
souls, he taught, are eternal, having existed before they 
came into bodies. In this pre-existence each soul saw aU 
pure ideas in a realm of perfect ideas. But, coming into the 
body is like entering a prison. The body clouds the soul 
and it forgets afl that it has seen. It is pulled down and 
debased by the body. 

' Thus, the goal of the soul, Plato held, is to free itself 
from the body in order that it may see truth dearly. Fur- 
ther, by certain experiences, the soul recalls the pure ideas 
which it saw in its pre-existent state. Knowledge, then, is 
not a new thing for the soul, but is simply a recall of what 
has been forgotten because of the body. 

* The human soul, then, is a part of pure reason. But it is 
debased by the body. However, since it existed before it 
came into the body, it may free itself from the body and 
continue to exist after the body has been destroyed. The 
soul, for Plato, is immortal. 

4 Plato offers several proofs of the immortality of the hu- 
man soul. In the first place, he holds, the soul is in abso- 
lutely simplest form and thus cannot be divided or de- 
stroyed. Further, the soul is life and it is not possible that 
life can become not-life. Life inust always remain life, and 
not-life must always remain not-life. Neither can become 
the other. 

Having a desire to possess a body, the soul, which had 



158 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GEEAT PHTLOSOPHEBS 

occupied a star, leaves its heavenly abode and enters into 
matter, or body. From then it has to struggle to free itself 
from the body. If it succeeds, it will return to its star and 
dwell there forever. But, if it fails, it will sink lower and 
lower, moving from one body to another. Here again is the 
familiar early idea of the transmigration of the soul. 

The ultimate goal of life, according to Plato, is release of 
the soul from the body so that it may return to its star and 
there spend eternity contemplating the beautiful and pure 
world of ideas. But, whether or not the soul succeeds in be- 
coming free from matter and its evils, it cannot be de- 
stroyed. The eternal pre-existence and immortality of the 
soul is a fundamental doctrine of Plato. 

ABISTOTLE taught that soul is to be found wherever there 
is life and, since everywhere in nature are to be found signs 
of life, soul must be throughout nature. If we examine na- 
ture we will find, so said Aristotle, a series of souls begin- 
ning with the lowest or plant souls and moving upward 
to the highest or human souk. Plant souls are concerned 
with eating and digesting food, or nutrition, and with the 
growth of the body as weD as with reproduction. The soul 
of man has additional and higher powers. 

As we study man, Aristotle held, we discover that his 
soul is very much like that of a plant in that it governs the 
life functions of the individual But it also resembles the 
animal soul in that by means of it man is able to receive 
sense impressions and deal with them. It is by means of 
this function of the soul that man comes into contact with 
and knows the world outside of his body. 

However, the human soul is higher, in that it has the 
power of thinking in terms of concepts, is able to think 
about the inner nature of things. Thus, the soul of man has 
the power of reason. This reason perceives concepts just as 
the lower part of the soul perceives objects in the world. 
Here Aristotle divides reason into that which he calls 
passive reason and that which he calls creative reason. The 
former is possibility which is turned into actuality by the 
latter. Just as throughout the universe Aristotle believed 
that matter and form were together so that form was con- 



THE SOXJL AND IMMORTAUTT 159 

stantly realizing itself in matter, a doctrine which we have 
discussed previously, so in the souL Here he taught that 
creative reason was the form and passive reason the matter. 

Creative reason, the form, existed, he held, before either 
body or soul were created. While passive reason, or the 
matter part of the soul, is connected with the body and 
will perish when the body is destroyed, creative reason is 
not influenced by the body, is immaterial, and will con- 
tinue to live after the death of the body. This creative rea- 
son is a spark of the divinity, a part of God, which comes 
into the soul from without and is not influenced by the 
baser side of the souL 

Since all but the creative reason perishes with the body, 
personal immortality is impossible in Aristotle's system* 
The only part of the soul which survives death is actually 
part of God and simply returns to God. All else perishes, 

The Position of the Later Greek Thinkers 

Since the Epicureans based their metaphysics on the 
work of Democritus, they were logically bound to hold 
that the soul is composed of atoms just like all other things 
in the universe. But, the atoms of the soul are extremely 
fine (thin) and are of various kinds* There are atoms of 
fire, air, breath, and very fine matter. These atoms are 
scattered throughout the body and are controlled by a 
rational part which, according to the Epicureans, is lo- 
cated in the breast Further, all sensations of the body are 
a result of the soul. 

Since the soul is, for these philosophers, material, it can- 
not be immortal. When the body dies and disintegrates, 
the soul atoms are scattered throughout the universe. 
Death, then, is the end for both body and souL As Lu- 
cretius, one of the later Epicureans, wrote, "A fool will not 
make more out of the hereafter than he has made of this 
life." 

The Stoics held that man is both soul and body, and 
that the soul is a spark from the divine fire controlled by a 
ruling part situated in the heart. It is a sort of blank tablet 
upon which things write by means of impressions just as 



l6o BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

one might write on a wax slab* This is the source of our 
knowledge. 

The soul of man, the Stoics taught, is the source of what 
we know as perception, judgment, feeling, and willing. At 
its best, it becomes rational, able to think in terms of con- 
cepts or ideas. Thus, the soul makes it possible for man to 
deliberate and make choices before he acts. 

Various Stoics held different ideas of immortality. Some 
taught that only the good and wise souls continued to exist 
after death of the body. All others perished with the body. 
Other Stoics held that all souk, regardless of their good- 
ness or badness, lived until the end of the world. 

The Views of Plotinus 

In PiLornNus we have an attempt to interpret the teach- 
ing of Plato in terms of the later religious interests. In doing 
this, Plotinus becomes one of the school known as Neo- 
platonism or the new Platonism. For Plotinus the human 
soul is part of a world soul. At first this human soul was 
in a realm where it saw the pure world soul and knew all 
that was good. But it turned toward matter and fell be- 
cause of its desire to mould matter. 

From this state of degradation, the soul must struggle 
to free itself from matter. If it fails, it must, at the time of 
the death of the body, enter another body of a man, a 
plant, or an animal.. However, to the extent it succeeds in 
freeing itself from matter, it returns to God and thereby 
realizes itself. 

Being part of the world soul, which is itself an emana- 
tion from God, the human soul is immortal, and will con- 
tinue to live after death. If it has not purified itself, it will 
continue to live in another body. If, however, it has been 
purified, it returns to the God of which it is a part and lives 
as does God. 

The Early and Medieval Christian Conception of the Soul 

Christianity, as interpreted by the Apologists, taught 

that the soul and body were separate things, and that the 

soul was that part of the individual which most nearly 



THE SOUL AND IMMORTALITY l6l 

represented the good in the universe. Thus, for them, the 
soul was immortal but continued to live in a resurrected 
body. Death, for these thinkers, was not a separation o 
body and soul, but rather a purification of the body so that 
it might be a fit place for the soul to dwell in throughout 
eternity. 

This point of view was developed further by AUGUSTINE 
who taught that man is a union of soul and body. But, for 
Lim, the body is a prison house of the soul, the source of 
all evil. The soul, on the other hand, is immaterial (not 
made of matter) and is wholly different and distinct from 
tike body. Although he taught that the soul directs and 
forms the body, he was unable to teH how this happens. 

Further, Augustine taught that each individual has his 
own soul, and that it is not an emanation from God. A 
soul does not exist before the body in which it dwells. How 
the soul was created was a mystery. However, after the 
soul came into being, it continued to live forever. The hu- 
man soul is, for Augustine, immortal. Nevertheless, the life 
of the soul after the death of the body may be either happy 
or miserable, depending upon how the individual lived 
during his earthly existence. If during this earthly exist- 
ence he has won the favor of God, he is given blessedness. 
If not, he is eternally condemned to misery. 

Throughout the so-called Dark Ages, in the teachings of 
the Schoolmen and their followers, the belief was held 
generally that man possesses a soul which is distinct from 
the body but which may be, in some way or other, in- 
fluenced by the body. Indeed, the eternal destiny of the 
soul was thought to depend to a degree at least upon its 
experiences while in the body. That the soul was immor- 
tal was not questioned Whether it had an existence before 
it entered the body, as those influenced by Plato had held, 
or whether it came into being at the time the body was 
created, there was no doubt that it lived eternally after 
the body perished. 

If good, the soul was rewarded by being permitted to 
continue its existence in a realm of complete blessedness. 
But, if the individual possessing the soul had lived an evil 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

life, the soul was condemned to eternal suffering and tor- 
ment. Immortality was certain in either case. Since the 
body was thought of as a source of evil and a danger to 
the soul, most thinkers held that the soul should, in so far 
as possible, free itself from the body and its temptations. 
In many instances, men sought ways to torture and deny 
the body so that the soul could live its own good life and 
thus prepare itself for an eternity of happiness. 

THOMAS AQUINAS was the philosopher who brought this 
general point of view into a complete and thorough state- 
ment. He taught that the human soul was created by God* 
This soul was, for him, immaterial, the intellectual and 
vital principle of the body. This intellectual soul was added 
to the body at birth. While there are other souls, the hu- 
man soul is different from all these in that it is intelligent 
and can will. 

This intelligent soul is not dependent upon the body fpr 
its existence or functioning, but can continue to act after 
the body has perished. Further, the soul continues to exist 
just as it did while the body was alive. Thus, it forms for 
itself a new body, a spiritual body through which it func- 
tions throughout eternity. 

This point of view was the pattern which orthodox Cath- 
olic Christianity accepted and made fundamental to its be- 
lief. Later Christian thinkers did not alter it in any signifi- 
cant detail. Heresies came forward from time to time, but 
were beaten back by the strength of the orthodox position. 

The Soul According to the Forerunners of the Renaissance 

LXJDOVICO VTVES, forerunner of the interest in science 
which marked the Renaissance, urged that doctrines 
should be abandoned and man should make a careful 
scientific study of the soul to discover, not its essence, but 
the manner in which it acts. BERNARDINO TELESIO at- 
tempted to explain the soul mechanically and materially 
in a way resembling the early Greeks. He held that the 
soul was a very fine substance, resembling heat, centered in 
the brain but diffused throughout the body through the 
nerves. As such, he believed the soul caused the parts of 



THE SOUL AND IMMORTALITY 163 

the body to remain together and to move as an individual. 
Besides this material soul, he held that an immortal soul 
existed, a soul added to the material soul by God. 

GIORDANO BRUNO taught that the soul was an immortal 
monad or uncaused element similar to the monads or ele- 
ments composing everything in the universe. 

These men, standing at the opening of the new age of 
mankind, the Modern Period, were not contented to ac- 
cept the theories of the soul developed by either the an- 
cients or the medieval Churchmen. They felt that these 
earlier theories and ideas did not stand the tests of science. 
Consequently, these men sought a theory of the soul and of 
immortality which would square with the new learning 
that was flooding in upon the age. 

The Views of Bacon and Hobbes 

The attempt to break with the past is clearly seen in the 
writings of FRANCIS BACON. He taught that the human 
soul was actually two souls, one divine or rational and the 
other irrational. The divine soul was, he held, a matter for 
religion to handle. The irrational soul, however, was open 
to study and understanding by man using the methods of 
science. By these methods Bacon believed that we would 
find this soul to be material but invisible, residing in the 
head and running along the nerves to all parts of the body. 
This soul was the seat of reason, imagination, understand- 
ing, memory, appetite, and will. 

HOBBES broke completely with the past. He held that 
the entire universe was material and that in such a universe 
there could be nothing corresponding to the human soul as 
described by earlier philosophers. His materialistic posi- 
tion left no room for an immaterial soul that could sur- 
vive the disintegration of the body. 

The Views of Descartes and Spinoza 

DESCARTES felt that the logical result of science was a 
mechanical and materialistic universe, but he was equally 
certain that this was not the complete explanation of the 
universe. Consequently, he was anxious to discover a way 



164 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

by which he could take account of all that science seemed 
to demand and at the same time hold to the existence of 
the human souL The result of this desire was his theory of 
one absolute substance, God, and two relative substances, 
mind and body. Having made this distinction, it was easy 
for him to maintain that the soul was distinct from the 
body and therefore not subject to the same laws as the 
body. 

The soul, he taught, is a unit or single principle which 
expresses itself in numerous ways. Among these are willing, 
feeling, and reasoning. Thus, the soul is seen as acting 
and also as having passions. 

Since this soul is part of the Whole, part of God or 
Absolute Substance, it cannot be thought of as disappear- 
ing, but continues as long as God continues. Death of the 
body is but a change, and the soul, being free of the body 
and never actually influenced by it, is not affected by its 
disintegration. 

Although Descartes held that God is the only substance, 
he felt it necessary to make a clear separation between 
soul and body and thus he left an ultimate dualism. This 
did not satisfy his followers. Two ways of solving the prob- 
lem were easily evident. On the one hand, a philosopher 
might turn away from the body and concentrate upon the 
soul. MAUEBRANCHE did just this. The soul was, for him, 
the only reality, and what we think of the body is merely 
an idea of the body in the soul. This is pure idealism. 
Hobbes had taken the other position: to deny the exist- 
ence of the soul and concentrate upon a materialistic view 
of the universe. 

It remained for SPINOZA to offer a solution of the prob- 
lem without sacrificing either the results of natural science 
or the soul. Since, for him, God was the only substance, 
the soul could be nothing else than a mode of God, As 
such, it was identified with tie spiritual side of the uni- 
verse. Soul was perceived when one looked at Substance 
from the side of mind rather than from the side of body. 
Thus, it was subject only to spiritual laws and not to the 
laws of science or of the material world. 



THE SOUL AND IMMOBTALITT 165 

Further, as a mode of the absolute substance, the soul 
could not be immortal in an individual sense, but it did 
have immortality as a mode of God which could not be 
destroyed any more than God could be destroyed, If it be 
a mode of God, it would of necessity continue even though 
the visible form of the body, also a mode of God, changed. 

Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Leibnitz 

The position of JOHN LOCKE resembles very much that 
of Descartes. He thought of the universe as being com- 
posed of two substances, bodies and souls. The souls, for 
him, are spiritual substances with the power of perceiving, 
thinking, and willing. Man arrives at the idea of soul by 
combining the various operations of the human mind, such 
as willing, knowing, and the like, and supposing a support 
for them. This support or ground is soul substance. His 
argument for this is: ^Having as clear and distinct ideas 
in us of thinking as of solidity, I know not why we may 
not as well allow a thinking thing without solidity, i.e., 
immaterial, to exist, as a sqlid thing without thinking, i.e., 
matter, to exist, especially since it is no harder to conceive 
how thinking should exist without matter than how mat- 
ter should think/* The soul is this immaterial thing which 
thinks. 

This soul of man is both active and passive for Locke. 
It is able to influence and move bodies and, at the same 
time, it is influenced by bodies so that it has ideas. Thus, 
the soul interacts with bodies. 

That the soul is immortal, lives after death of the body, 
is, for Locke, a matter of faith, and not anything of which 
we can have a clear and distinct idea. It is above reason, 
but can be believed on faith. 

Mind and soul are terms used interchangeably by 
BERKELEY. The universe, as we have seen, is, for him, all 
mind or spirit. Following Locke's position that all we can 
know are our ideas, Berkeley takes the thesis that mind, 
the creator and source of ideas, is all that exists. Ideas 
which are not the creation of the individual mind are the 
creation of God who is also mind. Thus, man's soul is the 



l66 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

beginning and end of the universe. And, of course, it can- 
not die but wiH live on as part of the spiritual essence of 
the universe. 

HUME, carrying lie Lockian position to its logical con- 
clusion, as be saw it, beld that we can bave no certain 
knowledge either of material or spiritual substance. We 
cannot know that either the outer world or the soul exists. 
AH we know is that there is a succession of ideas, one fol- 
lowing another. That there is a ground or support of these 
ideas, a soul which has them, cannot be known. We must 
therefore be agnostic (that is, without definite conviction) 
as regards the souL 

No investigation, Hume beld, will reveal an immaterial, 
indivisible, imperishable soul-substance. He writes, **When 
I enter intimately upon what I call myself, I always stum- 
ble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold* 
light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never 
catch myself, at any time, without a perception, and never 
can observe anything but the perception.** Mind, then, is 
nothing more than a succession or jumble of perceptions. 
Thus, any idea of the immortality of the soul is wholly 
without foundation and cannot be accepted. 

This line of reasoning was pure skepticism. As such it 
could not satisfy thinking men. Rather than accept it at its 
face value, philosophers were certain that somewhere 
along the line reaching from Locke to Hume there was 
something wrong, something important omitted. Thus, 
they set about searching for the mistake, the missing part 
which would make an entirely different picture. 

The position of LEIBNITZ seemed to many to offer more 
promise than the skepticism of Hume. The universe, for 
Leibnitz, is composed of an infinite number of monads or 
units of force. Even the soul is such a substance, a unit of 
spiritual force. Indeed, the soul atom is the model of all 
monads in the universe* 

The human organism differs from all other beings in 
that it contains in addition to other monads a "queen 
monad" or soul, which is the guide or controlling monad 
of all the other monads which make up the organism. This 



TOE SOUL AND IMMORTAUTJT l6/ 

soul monad organizes the monads of tie organism into a 
unity, a whole. But, this control which the soul monad 
has over all other monads of the hody is not a matter of 
direct influence. No monad can influence another. Rather, 
God has so created all monads that in man there is a pre- 
established harmony between soul monad and other mon- 
ads. As we see it, the soul monad seems to control other 
monads just as one man might control another. But this is 
an illusion. Actually the two act together because of this 
pre-existent harmony. 

The soul monad, just as all other monads, develops and 
moves toward self-realization because of its own nature, 
because of what it is internally. 

Further, all knowledge comes to the soul monad not 
from without, but from within itself. It is implicit within 
the soul and is a matter of the development of what is 
latent in the very nature of the soul itself. Experience sim- 
ply stirs the soul to realization of what is within it 

No monad can be destroyed, and this is therefore true 
of the soul monad. It is eternal, and therefore lives on even 
though the monads which make up a particular body sep- 
arate at death. The soul, then, is immortal. 

During the i8th century the influence of Leibnitz was 
strong in Germany, where philosophers were striving to 
prove the existence of the soul and its immortality. How- 
ever, in England, where the influence of Locke, Berkeley, 
and Hume was dominant, there was a trend toward a 
mechanistic theory of man and his universe. Here the idea 
that man was nothing more than a machine was prominent. 
Of course, such, an idea left no room for the conception of 
a soul. Men like Toland and Hartley strove to show that 
any idea of the soul was out of the question. 

The Soul and Immortality According to Kant 

It was KANT who drew the many strands of thought to- 
gether into a system which has proved to be one of the 
most important accomplishments in the history of human 
thought. Kant held that the understanding cannot know 
anything but that which is experienced. However, reason 



l68 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

can go beyond this and conceive of a world of which we 
can have no actual experience. Thus it transcends, rises 
above experience, and gives us transcendent principles. 

Reason gives man an idea of soul as the summation of 
all mental processes* Although we can never experience 
the soul, the idea of soul has value and therefore it is 
legitimate for us to think of it 

Since there can be no knowledge without a knower, it is 
legitimate for us to conclude that there is such a thing as 
a soul, and act as if it existed. Although we cannot prove 
the existence of an immortal soul, we may act as though 
one existed since there is real value in so doing. Kant held 
that this idea has regulative use in that it unifies many of 
our concepts, it systematizes many of our concepts or ideas. 
The Idea of a soul serves as a focal point to which we 
may refer our conscious experiences. 

Further, the idea of the soul has ethical value. It is a 
result of the moral law and serves as a basis for moral life. 
The moral law, which we have discussed previously, de- 
mands the good will, one so regulated that it acts always 
in such a way that its action might well become universal 
in principle at least. This good wiH must be realizable. But, 
man cannot become absolutely good at any moment dur- 
ing his mortal existence. Consequently, this principle makes 
the immortality of the soul necessary so that the demands 
of the moral law may be met. During this endless time 
made necessary and possible, the human soul goes on and 
on to perfection, to a complete realization of the demands 
of the moral law. 

Fichte, Schlelermacher, Herbart, and Schopenhauer 
Kant's contention that the moral law is the basis for act- 
ing as though there is a supersensible world, a world be- 
yond that of science, of experience, was the starting point 
of the philosophy of RCHTE. On this principle, Fichte and 
those who followed him built what has become known as 
post-Kantian idealism. The ego, or will, for Fichte, is the 
source, the creator of the world that we know. Man can 
understand only that which he has created. 



THE SOUL, AND IMMORTALITY l6g 

But, the ego is pure activity, universal reason, an ab- 
solute principle different from the ego of each individual. 
It is the basis for the individual ego, the ego of each per- 
son who lives. It is a universal life process dominating every 
individual consciousness. This ego is broken up into bits 
which are the egos of individual persons just as light 
might be broken up into bits but is not broken off from the 
source. Thus, that which is the individual self is but a 
manifestation of the universal ego or creative principle. 

This individual ego, because of the moral law which it 
finds within itself, as Kant had held, must go on struggling 
and therefore must be immortal. It is the part of the indi- 
vidual which others had called the soul and it cannot be 
thought of as dying with the body. 

Though unwilling to accept the doctrines of idealism to 
the same extent as Fichte, SCHLEIERMACHER. did, however, 
believe that the individual ego has an independence which 
makes it self-determining. It is able to develop its own par- 
ticular talent and thus contribute to the development of 
the Whole or the Absolute of which it is a part. But, even 
this freedom is not enough to admit of immortality of the 
ego or soul. The only immortality which Schleiermacher 
is willing to admit is that of union with the infinite. The 
soul, for him, is immortal when it becomes "eternal in 
every moment of time." 

HERBART opposed the entire idealistic point of view. For 
him, there are many simple, unchangeable "reals" or sub- 
stances which combine to form objects. The soul, he 
taught, is a real which may fee characterized as simple, 
absolute, timeless, and spaceless. The body of a man is a 
mass of reals with the soul established in the brain. Al- 
though all souls are essentially alike, they do differ in 
development due to the nature of the body in which each 
soul resides. 

As a soul bumps up against another soul sensations arise 
which are organized in the soul and form its content. 
Originally the soul is empty, and its furnishings are sensa- 
tions which result as the soul seeks to preserve itself in 
contact with other souls. 



170 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Since the world of reals is unchanging and the only 
change is a mixing and remixing of reals, the soul does not 
disappear when the body goes to pieces, but continues to 
exist. 

The "will" of SCHOPENHAUER corresponds to the soul o 
other philosophers. It is the *thing-in-itselF of Kant, the 
foundation beneath all experience, all things. And the indi- 
vidual will is immortal in that it is part of the universal 
will. At death the individual will ceases to be individual as 
a particular expression of the universal will. But will does 
not die. It is basic to all the universe, and will continue to 
be forever. 

The external world, according to RUDOLF HERMANN 
LOTZE, is a creation of the soul in the soul. This soul is 
situated in the brain and can contact the body only in the 
brain. While the body is alive, the soul is the ruling and 
controlling principle. After death of the body it is not 
dear, Lotze argues, what happens to the soul. However, he 
believes, as an act of faith, that each individual must some- 
time and somewhere receive his just reward or punish- 
ment Therefore, although he is not able to prove it, he 
does believe in some land of an immortality of the soul, 

Recent and Present-Day Conceptions of the 
Soul and Immortality 

More recent philosophy has abandoned the conception 
of soul and that of individual immortality. As one reads 
the pages of modern philosophers, one is struck with the 
fact that soul is seldom mentioned and the word "immor- 
tality" is almost never admitted. In a recent anthology of 
modern philosophy, a book of some 650 pages selected 
from the writings of the present-day philosophers, there is 
no mention of the soul and only a very few mentions of 
immortality. 

The position of most modern philosophers is that the 
body is able to act in certain ways which show a high de- 
gree of intelligence. This is called "minded action." Some 
few writers will use the general term "soul" to describe this 
action, but if they are pressed for a more accurate explana- 



THE SOOT- AND IMMORTAIXCY 

tion, will admit that they know nothing of a soul which is 
distinct from the body and which can daim anything like 
immortality, 

The basis for this general position is to be found in the 
present-day interest in science and the general conviction 
that it is dangerous to go beyond observable action. In- 
terest and respect characterize modern man's attitude to- 
ward the scientific method. This method, if applied care- 
fully, does not lead to the soul nor does it lead to a belief 
in immortality. 

The Behavioristic psychology as championed by John 
B. Watson and others centered modern attention upon be- 
havior as the thing to watch. Although many thinkers were 
not willing to go the whole limit of Behaviorism and ad- 
mit with its most enthusiastic advocates that behavior as 
seen by an observer is the beginning and end of a scientific 
study of man, nevertheless the influence of this position 
has been great. 

Further, the older attempt to account for man's ability 
to think and to reason on the basis of his possessing of a 
mind or soul has been largely abandoned. It is felt that 
such an explanation is no real explanation, but rather a 
dodging of the issue. Thought, it is held, is an activity 
with a certain quality, the quality of mindedness. Man 
who thinks does not have a mind distinct from the body 
with which he thinks. But^ because of his finer organiza- 
tion and construction, he is able to perform acts which are 
characterized as thinking. 

We find this general position taken by representatives of 
both the Postttvlstic and the Pragmatic schools of thought 
Among the Positivists is AUGUSTS COMTE who believed 
that the search for a soul and a belief in immortality were 
characteristics of an earlier and more childish stage of hu- 
man development As man becomes more mature in his 
racial development, he recognizes that such beliefs are not 
exact, that they are mere wishes which cannot be proven 
or founded upon fact Consequently, he argues, they must 
be abandoned. 

Pragmatism follows in this same tradition. WHJ-IAM 



172 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

JAMES recognized that many men believe in the existence 
of a soul which has immortality and that such a belief has 
a certain usefulness in man's moral life. But he was not 
able to make a place for this belief within the structure of 
careful thought. JOHN DEWEY is more certain than was 
James that there is no basis for such beliefs. Indeed, he is 
convinced that the doctrine of the soul may be definitely 
harmful since it carries a load of tradition which weights 
man down or causes him to give up altogether the at- 
tempt to understand experience which has the quality of 
the religious. 

While there still remain many philosophers, influenced 
almost to a man by the religious tradition, who attempt to 
interpret the term *souT and the accompanying term "im- 
mortality** in such a way that both can be fitted into the 
scheme of modem science without too much twisting and 
turning, the modem trend is toward abandoning the ideas 
altogether as far as philosophy is concerned. 

Soul is held to be nothing more than a name for a kind 
of activity, an activity which is spiritual It does not mean 
an entity or thing which one may possess as he possesses 
hands, eyes, and the like. Further, immortality does not 
mean for most modern philosophers the eternal continuing 
of a thing or the eternal living of the individual entity 
which we know as ourselves. Biological immortality or the 
continued existence of the germ structure of man, the im- 
mortality of influence or the continued effect of one's in- 
fluence after his body has died, and the immortality of the 
group or the continuation of the whole of which each in- 
dividual is for a time a part, are positions taken by modern 
thinkers. 

But the older traditional idea that there is a dualism of 
body and mind or soul, both entities with more or less 
separate lives, has been almost wholly abandoned. Thus, 
the conception that one member of such a dualism, the 
mind or soul, can continue to live and function after the 
other member has ceased to function has been abandoned 
also. 

In the place of these traditional ideas, conceptions which 



THE SOTIL AND IMMORTALITY 1/3 

have a long and honored tradition, we find today the more 
scientific conception that man is a being who, because of 
his long and highly specialized evolutionary development, 
is able to do certain things wholly impossible at any other 
level of the evolutionary process* He is able to reason, 
think, plan and carry out the results of his planning, is able 
to conceive spiritual values and strive for their realization, 
He is able to make fine adjustments to his environment. 
Indeed, he is able to conceive the universe in the compass 
of his thought and make far-flung plans to master it and 
turn it to his desires. These abilities are far above anything 
which we know in the universe. Thus, they have a quality 
different from that of any other activities which man 
knows. However, modern thought is not willing to go from 
these facts to the theory that such acts are not the result of 
body but are rather the result of another thing which 
man has and which can be called mind or soul. Modern 
thought holds that these activities are minded or spirit- 
ual activities, and part of the complete activity of the 
individual. 

An illustration will help to make this position clearer. 
One man will be called ugly while another will be called 
handsome. What, modern philosophers ask, produces the 
difference? Does the second of the two men possess a thing 
which we may term ^beauty,** and because of which he is 
beautiful? No. Beauty is not a thing, but a quality. Be- 
cause the features of one individual are so constructed and 
organized, we say he is beautiful. There is no thing, no 
entity > such as "beauty" which makes one individual 
beautiful. 

Likewise, man does not have a soul or a mind. Rather, 
his acts are of such a nature that we characterize them as 
minded or spiritual. 

This position makes it necessary for modern philosophy 
to abandon the idea of immortality as it has been held in 
the past. If there is no thing, no entity, which corresponds 
to the soul, then there can be no immortality of the soul. 
This necessitates the abandonment of the conception of a 
place where souls go after death. This conception extends 



174 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GRKAT FHILOSOPHEBS 

all the way from the old Hebrew idea of Sheol, and the 
Greek idea of Hades, the land of the shades across the 
river Styx, to the highly imaginative idea of Heaven held 
by the Christian tradition. Indeed, almost every religion 
has held to the belief in a land beyond the grave where 
good souls go to receive and to enjoy their reward. Many 
religions have also conceived of another land to which the 
evil souls go to receive their punishment. But, if there is no 
soul, there can be no lands of reward and punishment. 
Modern thought, therefore, turns to man and to his life 
between birth and the grave, for a locus (that is, locality 
or realm) of its values. Within this span the modern phi- 
losopher finds all that he needs in order to understand 
man. Many individual thinkers will allow for beliefs or 
hypotheses regarding after-grave experiences, but they do 
not include them in their philosophic schemes, nor can 
they find sufficient evidence to make such beliefs other 
than hang-overs from an older and less scientific tradition 
or the wishes of those who are not satisfied with the 
scientific interpretation of life. 



Chapter VII 
MAN AND THE STATE 

PYTHAGORAS DEMOCEITUS THE SOPHISTS 

SOCRATES PLATO ARISTOTLE 
THE EPICUREANS THE STOICS AUGUSTINE 

MACHLAYELLI GROTTUS HOBBES 

LOCKE ADAM SMITH ROUSSEAU HEGEL 

MARX MILL NIETZSCHE PEWEY 



Is society made for man or is man made for society? 
Js the state a divine creation which man must not 
question, or is it a result of a "social contract" among 
men and subject to change when it no longer serves 
men? How do the rulers get their authority? Is revolu** 
tion justifiable? Is totalitarianism or democracy cor- 
rect? 



Man is a gregarious being. By nature Be lives with Bis 
fellows and likes it Indeed, no more cruel punishment can 
be inflicted upon an individual than to isolate him from 
other men for a long period of time. 

Whether this love of being with other men is due to 
man's basic and original nature, no one can say. However, 
it is clear that the earliest men of whom we know anything 
lived together. It may have been in a cave, or it may have 
been in rude shelters constructed of branches and leaves, 
or it may have been squatting beneath a tree or in the 
protection of some overhanging cliff; but wherever it was, 
the most primitive of men wanted to be near those of their 



176 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

kind. The reason may have been the inherent desire for 
security and the realization that one man alone is danger- 
ously exposed to his enemies, while two or more men to- 
gether are better able to protect themselves. 

But, whatever the reason and whatever the location, 
wherever we find evidence of man we find evidence of a 
number of men and women all living in a group. And, 
since all living together, whether it be of man or of beast, 
brings conflicts of purpose and desire, it is almost certain 
that the earliest of men organized some form of society, 
established some rules which were accepted by each one. 
Probably the first rules were not consciously determined or 
set down so that all might learn. They were possibly ac- 
cepted as right and necessary without much if any thought 
on the matter* 

It was out of these simple provisions for living together 
that the first social requirements grew. Gradually an ac- 
cepted body of customs and procedures evolved. These 
became tribal laws or rules of the social group. Those pro- 
cedures which were found to preserve the group and pro- 
tect it against enemies without and within were held to 
tenaciously, while those which did not serve this purpose 
were abandoned. 

By this process tribal or group organizations developed 
with their ways of living which were handed on from the 
older generation to the younger. Some of these rules were 
learned by the young as they lived day by day among 
their fellows. They saw others act in certain ways and ac- 
cepted these ways as right Otter rules were transmitted 
to the young in solemn ceremonies conducted by the mem- 
bers of the group on special occasions, the chief of which 
was that conducted when the young man was admitted 
into full membership in the tribe at puberty. 

These unwritten customs and laws held the group to- 
gether solidly, and anyone who dared to disobey even in 
the least was severely punished. Often death was the pen- 
alty for failure to follow the tradition. Here was a closely 
knit society, with laws, customs, and penalties, a society 



MAN AND THE STATE 177 

which passed on its traditions to each generation by ex- 
ample, word of mouth, and ceremonial rites. 

Then came the time when these laws and customs were 
written down and a code of laws resulted, laws which were 
binding because they had proved themselves to be neces- 
sary for the preservation of the life of the social group. 
These were the beginnings of society and the state. 

It was many centuries later that the philosophers turned 
their attention to this social organization and asked how 
it came into being and what was its nature and meaning. 
**Is it," they asked, *a natural result of man's living to- 
gether, or does it have divine origin? Is it a mere con- 
venience which is to be changed and revised as times 
change, or does it Iiave a permanent status such that man 
changes it at his peril? Where is the power of the state, 
in the people or in the rulers who receive it from God? 
What is the best form of the state, and how shall man 
attain this?" 

These questions and many others have occupied the at- 
tention of many of the great philosophers. Not only have 
they been the cause of much philosophic speculation, but 
they have served to stir men to wars and threats of war. 
Revolutions have arisen because men have differed in their 
answers to these questions and have been willing to die to 
prove that they were right. In our own time men have 
fought world-engulfing wars because they were unable to 
agree as regards the answers to some of these questions. 

The ancients believed that their gods were the ultimate 
rulers of the state, and that those of their fellows who held 
power over them had received their authority directly from 
the gods. Further, they accepted without question the 
belief that all the laws by which they lived were given to 
their ancestors by the gods and therefore could not be 
changed even in tie least. 

Illustrative of this position is the belief of the early He- 
brews that Moses, their great lawgiver, received the laws 
written on tablets of stone from their god, Yahweh (Jeho- 
vah) . The Ten Commandments, the basis of their law, was 
believed to have divine origin, and Yahweh was their only 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

ruler. Mcses and the others who ruled over them did not 
hold this position by their own power but as representa- 
tives of f ahweh. Punishment for breaking the laws was not 
man-given, but was inflicted by Yahweh. 

All early peoples held these same beliefs, substituting the 
name of their god for the Yahweh of the Hebrews. They 
saw the state as a divine creation and the laws as divine 
commands which man broke at his peril since divine pun- 
ishment was sure and just The god was made angry and 
wreaked vengeance upon those who dared disregard his 
will 

The early Greeks did not have their laws written on 
tablets of stone but rather in the minds of their leaders. 
The customs of their forefathers, customs developed 
through generations of tribal and group experience, were 
passed on to the group and interpreted and enforced by 
the old men. In time these customs were brought together 
and written down by Lycurgus. Here the rules for living 
together in a group or state were presented clearly so that 
everyone would know what they were and could obey 
them. 

Among all these early peoples the group or the state 
was more important than any member or citizen. These 
ancient people recognized that the individual man could 
not live long and could not enjoy many advantages unless 
he lived in a group. Further, they realized that the great- 
est good for the greatest number depended upon the 
preservation of the group as a unit Consequently, anyone 
who by his acts threatened the safety of the group com- 
mitted a crime deserving of the most severe punishment. 
It was necessary, they saw, to preserve the group even 
at the expense of the individual. When the individual and 
the group came into conflict, it was the individual who 
had to yield or be destroyed. It would be fatal to all if 
the group was destroyed, 

The State as Viewed by the Early Greek Philosophers 

The Pijthagoreans, representative of this early point of 
view among the Greeks, taught that the individual should 



MAN AND THE STATE 179 

subordinate himself to the whole and should act at aH 
times for the good of the state. Thus they taught their 
members respect for authority, the laws and civic virtues of 
the times, and the ideal of sacrifice for the good of the 
whole. 

This same general position was taken by DEMOCBITOS. 
He held that each one should devote himself wholly to 
the good of the state because *a weD-administered state 
is our greatest safeguard. 1 * In another place he wrote, 
'When the state is in a healthy condition, all things pros- 
per; when it is corrupt, all things go to ruin * Since, he 
argued, the ultimate welfare of everyone depended upon 
the state, it was but reasonable to hold that the welfare 
of the state was man's first concern. 

After the Persian Wars (500 to 449 B.C.) Athens be- 
came the center of ancient Greek culture. The events lead- 
ing up to these wars and the developments during the 
wars developed in the Athenians, among other peoples 
of the times, an interest in the problems of government and 
an interest m the democratic form of human living. This 
led naturally to a growth of independent thinking which 
eventually resulted in a growing concern for theories of 
government Men began to question the older blind loy- 
alty to the powers of the state, and many began to assert 
their own independence and their right to a life more or 
less free from the dominance of the established govern- 
ment Individualism was in the air. Some suggested that 
man should divorce himself from the authority of the group 
and hold himself free to challenge the group and criticize 
freely the older traditions. 

The Sophists, as we have pointed out before, led this 
advance into individualism. They centered attention not on 
the group, but upon the individual member of the group. 
They asserted his ultimate worth and independence. They 
proposed to teach the individual how to succeed, how to 
gain his own ends, tinder the law, and even to dodge the 
law by skillful argument 

Indeed, there were Sophists who argued that the kws 
were mere inventions of the weaker members of the group, 



ISO BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHEBS 

of society, to enslave and Bold down the stronger. In Pla- 
to's dialogue entitled Gorgfas, a well-known Sophist argues 
that *The makers of the laws are the majority who are 
weak; and they make laws and distribute praises and cen- 
sures with a view to themselves and their own interests; 
and they terrify the stronger sort of men, and those who 
are able to get the better of them, ia order that they may 
not get the better of them," He goes on to assert that the 
great men of history have been those who refused to obey 
the kws of the weak majority who have organized to hold 
them down. The bail which they held before the people of 
Athens was stated by CaDides in this way: Tf there were a 
man who had sufficient force, he would shake off and break 
through, and escape from all this; he would trample under- 
foot all our formulas and spells and charms and all our 
laws which are against nature." This was a challenge to the 
spirit of independence which was abroad in the land to 
assert itself and refuse longer to be repressed by the weak, 
the ignorant, and the fools. 

It is obvious that this position might easily be inter- 
preted as a call to anarchy, an incentive to rebellion against 
all authority. And many individuals took it for just that* 
Thus, much of the Sophist influence led to unreasoned re- 
fusal to be subject to the dictates of the group and thus 
threatened the solidarity of the Athenian state. But, there 
were many Sophists who did not intend that this should 
happen. They were not satisfied with the older traditional 
idea that man should be subject to the state wholly and un- 
conditionally, and against this they rebelled. But they did 
not want to go to the other extreme of complete anarchy 
(that is, lack of any form of government). The tragedy of 
their thinking was that although they saw the problem and 
the danger in the traditional philosophy of the state, they 
were unable to counter this tradition with something better. 
They were not able to offer a solution to the problem of 
society which would make for social unity and at the same 
time avoid blind subservience to the state. 

However, in their efforts to solve this problem they 
etched clearly on the minds of their age the issues involved, 



MAN AND THE STATE l8l 

and challenged better minds than theirs to attempt a solu- 
tion. They made it impossible for those philosophers who 
followed them to dodge the problem of developing an 
adequate philosophy of the state. And the great minds who 
worked during the next two hundred years made many 
significant contributions to a solution of the problem. 

The State According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 

SOCRATES first asked the important questions involved in 
the problem. Xenophon, in his Memorabilia, recounts that 
Socrates never tired of asking of everyone he met, "What 
is a state? What is a statesman? What is a ruler over men? 
What is a ruling character?* Although he did not answer 
these questions, he laid the basis for answering them in his 
major position that the greatest concern of any citizen 
should be knowledge. The good citizen was one who con- 
stantly searched for true knowledge, who was forever ques- 
tioning. When, Socrates argued, a man discovers true 
knowledge, he will act on it and will conduct himself 
rightly in all his relations with his fellows. 

Although Socrates saw defects in the Athenian state and 
spent a good deal of his time pointing to them and criti- 
cizing the rulers for their mistaken ideas about government, 
he was intensely loyal to Athens. When he had been con- 
demned to death by the Athenian courts, a condemnation 
which he with many others believed to be wholly unjust, 
he refused the offer of his friends to bribe the guards and 
escape. His argument was that should he do that he would 
be breaking the laws of the state and thus making it that 
much weaken The state, despite its mistakes, was to him a 
mother who had given him life and had made him what 
he was. He could no more betray the state th*n he could 
betray his mother. His method was not that of rebellion. 
Nor would he accept exile and turn away from the state. 
Rather, he counseled his followers to remain loyal to the 
state, and through this loyalty to help the state correct its 
faults and mistakes. 

The illustrious pupil of Socrates, PLATO, took up the 
problem where Socrates had left it and endeavored to 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT 3PH3LOSOPHERS 

find a solution. He held that the state was necessary for 
the highest development of the individual. Goodness, for 
him, was not goodness in isolation, but was goodness in 
the group. The good man was the good citizen. Thus, the 
state should be so constructed that it would make possible 
the good life for sSL 

He argued that the individual should subordinate him- 
self to the state, but that this was simply a means by which 
the individual could reach his most perfect development. 
The good of each man, he believed, was tied up with the 
good of the group. Laws were necessary only because some 
people refused to co-operate with the good state. They 
served to bring these people in line and thus make the 
whole good. 

In the state, he argued, the best minds and the finest 
souls should rule. They formed a class of philosopher- 
mlers whose authority should not be questioned by the 
rest of the group. He believed that since they were philoso- 
pher-rulers their rule would be good and just. They could 
understand the right, and would do it without question. 
The rest of the members of the state he would place in 
classes suited to their talents. Those who had a talent for 
war should be placed in the warrior class. Those who had 
a talent for mercantile pursuits would be in the trade and 
merchant class. The skves should be placed in the slave 
class. Plato believed that such an organization would give 
the best possible state and that in it each individual, doing 
his assigned Job to the best of his ability, would be happy 
and would develop to his fullest 

This ideal state is developed in Plato's famous book, the 
Republic. In a book written somewhat later, the Laws, he 
argues that all citizens should have a voice in the govern- 
ment and that all work should be turned over to the slaves. 

This theory of the state is fundamentally aristocratic. 
Plato was wealthy, a son of the most favored class in 
Athens. Being such, he never was able to be wholly dem- 
ocratic, but aligned himself with the more aristocratic 
thought of his day. Further, his theory was socialistic in 
that it provided for complete control by the state of the 



MAN AND THE STATE 183 

lives of its members. The wealth of all was to be devoted 
to the use of all as tiey needed and deserved it, and the 
rulers could say in what class each individual should work 
and live. The state was supreme, but this doctrine was 
robbed of its sting by his added argument that in such a 
state each person would be happy and develop to his 
fullest. 

ARISTOTUS, the pupil of Plato, developed a philosophy of 
the state which resembled that of his teacher very much. 
He held that man is by nature a social animal and, as such, 
can realize his truest self only in society and among his 
land. Although the earliest forms of social living were the 
family and later the community, the goal of social evolu- 
tion was, for Aristotle, the city state such as was known in 
Greece during his lifetime. 

Since Aristotle believed, as we have pointed out before, 
that the whole is prior to its parts, he held fhat the state 
was prior to the individual member of the state. The indi- 
vidual is born into the state which has existed long before 
he became a member. But, the goal of the state, he main- 
tained, is to produce good citizens. Therefore, it should be 
organized and conducted so that it enables each member 
to become wholly good. To the extent that tihe state does 
not enable the individual to live a virtuous and happy life, 
it is evil. 

Any constitution, he argued, should be adjusted to the 
nature and the needs of the members of the particular 
group. But, in any group there are individuals who are 
unequal in many ways. Therefore, a good constitution must 
recognize these natural unequalities and confer rights ac- 
cordingly. In so far as all men are equal, the constitution 
must confer equal rights, but in so far as they are unequal, 
it must confer unequal rights. Among the uaequalities 
which he would recognize are those erf personal abilities, 
property, birth, and freedom. You treat slaves differently 
from free men and those born of slaves differently from 
those born of free men. 

Aristotle held that a monarchy, an aristocracy, and a 
"polity** in which the members are nearly equal, are the 



184 BASIC TEACHINGS OF C3REAT PHILOSOPHERS 

best f onns of the state. On the other hand he condemned 
as bad a tyranny, an oligarchy, and a democracy. 

Aristotle believed that slavery was a just practice in a 
good state since it was, for him, a natural institution. How- 
ever, he would admit only foreigners to the slave class. He 
took this position because he held foreigners of all nations 
to be inferior to the Greeks and thus not fit to enjoy the 
same rights as Greeks. 

Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle were all unable to solve the 
problem of the state and the individual. Their theories were 
interesting on paper, and many thoughtful men of that 
time studied them and were interested. But the spirit of 
individualism as championed by the Sophists was sweep- 
ing Greece, and each man was concerned primarily with 
himself and his own success. Slowly but surely the unity of 
the state was destroyed. Individualism was no pathway to 
unity against the enemies of Athens and other Greek city 
states. As a result, these enemies were successful and the 
Greek city states fell under their yoke one after another, 
Athens, Corinth, and Sparta, the three great Greek city 
states, fell, and eventually all Greece came under the dom- 
ination of Philip of Macedon at the battle of Chaeronea in 
338 B.C. Individualism had proved an internal poison 
which eventually so weakened the Greek city states that 
they could offer no effective resistance to their enemies and 
their fall was inevitable. 

The Positions of the Later Greek Thinkers 

Amid the gradual crumbling of the city states of Greece 
the Epicureans sought to develop a theory of the state 
which would fit the situation. They taught that all social 
life is based on the self-interest of the individual. We be- 
come members of a social group simply because we find 
that in such a group we can get more for ourselves, be- 
cause the group will give us better protection from our 
enemies. Therefore, there can be no absolute justice or 
natural rights and laws. That is good which men agree to 
call good. The laws are simply rules which the group ac- 
cepts and by which the members are willing to live. If the 



MAN AND THE STATE l8$ 

members of the group decide that a certain law is no longer 
of value in getting what they want, it can be changed or 
thrown out altogether. 

Injustice is not an evil in itself, they held. We are just, 
only because it helps us to be so. When obedience to laws 
does not help us longer, we may break the laws, if we can 
escape punishment. 

The Epicureans did not believe that participation in pub- 
lic life would contribute to the happiness of tfie individual; 
therefore, they held that the wise man would shun public 
office and public responsibility as much as possible. This 
position, as is evident, is one of pure individualism and 
selfishness. The individual associates himself with others 
only because it is to his advantage to do so, and he breaks 
away from the group and its requirements as soon .is it is 
to his advantage to do so. Further, the individual helps the 
group and participates in group responsibility only to the 
degree that it is to his advantage to do so. This point of 
view certainly does not build strong group loyalty or sol- 
idarity. It is the complete opposite of the earlier Greek 
position of loyalty to the state. Indeed, it is a clear expres- 
sion of the doctrine of ''enlightened self-interest.'* Each 
person is told that he is to make his own happiness, and 
that alone, the goal of all that he does. 

The Stoics took a position wholly opposite to that of the 
Epicureans as regards man's relationship to the group. 
They held that man is more than merely an individual in- 
terested in his own welfare. He is also an individual with 
an inborn social impulse which makes necessary group 
life. Indeed, all men are members of a great cosmic society, 
the universal state. We all have duties and obligations in 
this state, and its laws are the natural laws which we must 
all obey whether we like it or not. 

The Stoic state is universal and thus dominates every 
individual completely. Indeed, each member must l>e will- 
ing at all times to sacrifice himself for the good of the 
state. Individual interests are always subordinate to the 
interest of the whole, and the state must be preserved at 
all cost. 



3.86 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Thus, the Stoics taught that everyone should participate 
in public affairs and contribute as much as possible to the 
welfare of the group. However, and this is most important, 
the Stoics never taught a narrow nationalism in which a 
small state could be superior to the general* welfare of 
humanity. Hie good state was, for them, one whose laws 
and practices were in harmony with the good of all man- 
kind and with the natural laws of the universe. 

The Stoic, then, was to be a universal citizen, a member 
of the Great Society which includes all men and the laws 
of which are the universal laws of nature itself. Each man 
must subordinate himself to the universal ideal and live in 
such a way as to serve the good of all men wherever they 
might be. A world society rooted in nature was their ideal 
This was, obviously, wholly different from the position of 
the Epicureans and the other individualists of the day, and 
was equally opposed to the position of those who would 
have mar* subordinated to a particular state or social group. 
The Stoic ideal of universal brotherhood was the highest 
point to which the thought of the Greek period arose, and 
to which other thinkers in days to come were to strive. 

Indeed the Stoics taught much which has become cen- 
tral in modern thought With the loss of Greek independ- 
ence they began to look at all men as brothers and to teach 
universal brotherhood and equal rights for all men. They 
sensed the doctrine of the solidarity of the human race 
and the dignity of man regardless of his position in society, 
his wealth, his birth, or his education. Their position may 
be summed up in the words, ''Virtue despises no one, 
neither Greek nor barbarian, man nor woman, rich nor 
poor, freeman nor slave, wise nor ignorant, whole nor sick." 
This was certainly dose to our modern view. 

The Views of the Early Christian Thinkers 
This point of view was also central in the thinking of 
most of the Christian thinkers and philosophers. For them 
God was the Father of all mankind, thus making all men 
brothers. The Christian community was a social group in 
which the customary distinctions of race and social status 



MAN AND THE STATE 187 

were eliminated. Further, the Christians thought of the 
temporal state as an institution subject to God and de- 
riving its power from God. Man, therefore, was loyal to 
the state only in so far as it obeyed the laws of God. His 
first loyalty was to God. 

However, in the thinking of many, the temporal state 
had so far failed to square itself with the will of God that 
man was more or less free from any obligation to it The 
"contempt of the world,* which characterized the meta- 
physics of many of the Apologists, likewise characterized 
their attitude toward the state. The corruption of tie age 
drove many to seek a life of seclusion from the state in the 
monastic life. They turned from social obligations to a per- 
sonal striving to save their souls through a life of isolation 
and contemplation. 

Throughout most of the early Christian period loyalty to 
God and His laws was first in the thinking of the Christians. 
In so far as the state was obedient to God, they could be 
loyal to it also. 

But, with the development of the Church as an institu- 
tion and with the spread of Christianity throughout the 
Roman Empire, it became necessary for Christian thinkers 
to revise their notions regarding government and human 
associations. For a while we find Christian writers hesi- 
tating between the older contempt for the world and the 
things of the world and the opposite attitude of interest in 
the world and all that it contained. In SAINT AUGUSTINE, 
for example, this inability to make a choice between world 
denial and world affirmation is remarkably evident 

While AMBROSE, an earlier dhurch thinker, had held the 
possession of property and wealth to be ^damnable,* Au- 
gustine admitted that one had a right to gain wealth. But, 
he did feel that such wealth might be a hindrance to the 
Christian life. 

In Augustine's theory of the State we find the same in- 
ability to decide between the world and contempt for the 
world. For him the state is based on self-love and often 
leads to a contempt for God and all his laws. But the "City 
of God** is based upon contempt for the self and complete 



l88 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHELOSOPHEBS 

love for God. Thus, his ideal is this City of God. Neverthe- 
less, he writes that the state is an ethical community and 
that its chief end is the happiness of mankind. In it justice 
may rule. 

Despite this hanging, as it were, between two states, 
Augustine holds firmly to the position that the Church, as 
a worldly incarnation of the City of God, is to be supreme 
over the state, and the head of the Church is to rule over 
the rulers of the states. Further, while the ruler of the state 
may make mistakes, the ruler of the Church can never 
make a mistake. His word and his rule are infallible since 
he is the representative of God on earth. 

Thus, while Augustine feared the state and saw in 
it dangers to the soul of man, he was never able to turn 
his back on it completely and condemn it as wholly sinful 
The older Christian contempt for the world haunted Trim, 
but was never able to master him completely. Although 
the monastic life was for him the ideal, he was practical 
enough to realize that most men could not attain the ideal 
and thus had to do the best they could as members of a 
temporal state. 

The Views cj tine Medieval Christian Thinkers 

During the so-called Dark Ages, after the northern tribes 
had overrun the Roman Empire and destroyed a great deal 
of the culture and social organization of the first four cen- 
turies of the Christian era, the principle of authority was 
supreme. During the entire Middle Ages man was subject 
to some authority. The state and its rulers assumed con- 
trol over the people, so man found himself everywhere 
under the command of some authority. Thus obedience to 
the law, whatever its source, became a settled practice. 

Gradually there grew up the idea that the king received 
his authority from God and thus could not be questioned. 
Any disobedience to him was actually disobedience to the 
supreme authority of the universe, God, Indeed, authority 
was superior to public opinion and the state superior to 
the individual. Here the individualism of the later Greeks 



MAN AND THE STATE l8{) 

was conquered completely, and in its place stood almost 
complete domination of the individual by the state. 

The flanking of the Schoolmen, as was pointed out ear- 
lier, was confined to Interpreting the dogmas of the 
Church. Although they were at times keen of mind, these 
philosophers were confined within the walls of Church doc- 
trine and tradition and had to spend their talents in careful 
analysis of the meanings of these. Thus, their thinking 
about the state and the place of man in the social structure 
was limited by what the Church was willing to accept as 
authentic. 

But, as in all ages, while the great majority of thinkers 
followed the standard pattern, there were those who, often 
without understanding the entire import of their thought, 
planted the seeds of a later breakdown of tradition* 

Among the Scholastics were two groups known as the 
Realists and the Nominalists. The Realists held that tihe 
whole was the only real thing, and that the parts, the units, 
were not truly real The Nominalists held that the parts, 
the units, were the real things, and the whole merely a 
name. Applied to our immediate problem, the State, this 
would mean that the Realists held the State to be the only 
reality, and its members, men and women, to be mere 
units with no true reality. The Nominalists, on the other 
hand, held man to be the true reality, and the State a mere 
aggregation of men which had no existence or reality of 
its own apart from its members* 

The logical result of these two strains of thought was 
that some would hold that the real authority rested in the 
State as the only reality while others would hold that the 
real authority rested in the individual man and not in the 
State. Realism and Nominalism were doctrines applicable 
to the problem of the State and its members. 

JOHN Scorns EBIGENA was a realist. Although he did 
not work out his doctrine in its application to the state, he 
conceived of the universal, the whole, existing prior to the 
particular individual. Thus he was in the tradition of Plato 
and Aristotle and those others who saw the state as even- 
tually supreme and prior to any individual member. 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Likewise AXSELM was in this realistic tradition. He de- 
voted much time and thought to proving that universals 
were prior to individuals. 

ROSCEUN represents the other point of view. He taught 
that the individual is the only reality and that any univer- 
sal is nothing more than a mere name for a group of in- 
dividuals. Take away the individuals and you have noth- 
ing but a name left No reality remains. 

As with any two extreme positions, and Realism and 
Nominalism, were extreme positions, there arises sooner or 
later someone who seeks to effect a compromise. ABELABD 
was that man at this time. His theory has been called **con- 
ceptualism/* He taught that universals cannot be realities 
apart from things, but that they are concepts in the mind 
of man. He was interested particularly in things and wanted 
to point with emphasis to them, but recognized that ideas 
erf groups had a certain reality in the mind of man. 

Thus, for him, the individual was extremely important, 
but the group had its importance also and could not be 
ruled out altogether. Both were significant factors in any 
understanding of man and his relations with his fellows* 

Thus, the thinkers of the Middle Ages planted the seeds 
which were to destroy the supreme authority of the social 
group. After this doctrine had won out over that of in- 
dividualism and had dominated man's thinking for several 
centuries, the spirit of individualism again asserted itself 
and began to demand recognition. Gradually it gained the 
ascendency and man began once more to question the 
authority that ruled him. 

THOMAS AQUINAS, the last of the great Church thinkers 
of the Middle Ages, sought to fuse the thinking of Aristotle 
with that of Augustine. He taught that man is naturally a 
political being and seeks to be in society. Further, the su- 
preme purpose of the state was, for him, the good of the 
group. This can be attained only if the society is strongly 
united and is able to present a solid front against its ene- 
mies. Thus a monarchy in which the rule is strongly cen- 
tralized is, for him, the best form of government. But this 



MAN AND THE STATE 1Q1 

government must not be oppressive of the members. There 
must be no tyranny. 

Rebellion against the government can never be justified, 
St Thomas Aquinas taught that any change in government 
should come through legal means, since government is of 
divine origin. If it is not possible for the member to obtain 
redress of his grievances through legal means, he must 
leave the matter to God who will work out good in the end. 

But Aquinas held that the church was superior to the 
state and the ruler of the state was to be always obedient 
to the ruler of the church. The state, then, was thought of 
as an institution divinely established and drawing its power 
over men from God through His church. Man's ultimate 
loyalty was to the church and God, but he had to obey 
the state since the state in turn received its power from the 
church. 

The position of JOHN DUNS Scores is interesting in that 
it is developed upon the premise that God is absolutely 
free and supreme. Society is a creation of God and is what 
it is because God has made it so. God could have made 
another type of society just as well and could have made 
different laws. Then this type would have been right and 
its laws just. This is a far cry from the Sophistic conception 
of the state as a result of an agreement among men and its 
laws as established because men wanted them so. The 
state, for Scotus, is a creation of God, not of necessity but 
of his own free wilL It is as it is because God wiUs it so. 
Thus, man must obey the kws of the state or suffer divine 
punishment. 

Although Scotus did not foresee the result, this theory 
gave great power to existing states and rulers. They could 
claim direct authority from God and could use the fear of 
eternal punishment to enforce their authority. 

But man was not contented to accept this domination of 
the state even though it was based upon the theories of 
great churchmen. The nominalistic position persisted and 
there were those who arose constantly to assert the freedom 
of the individual over the authority of the state. WUJJAM 
OF OCCAM was one of this group. He stressed the reality of 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

the individual and thereby gave man a strong argument 
for asserting his dignity and for questioning the power of 
the state when it seemed to violate the will of its members. 
This, along with other things, led to a growing battle 
between the state and the church. Men arose to hold that 
the state was a temporal institution receiving its power and 
authority from the governed and thus free from any domi- 
nation by the church. At times the church was in the saddle 
and ruled the states then existing. At other times the states 
overcame the church and asserted their freedom. 

The State as Viewed by the Forerunners of the Renaissance 

It was at this time that man began to assert his own 
freedom and to challenge the power of rulers who held 
key positions in the state. The democratic spirit was afoot 
in the land, and absolute rule was being effectively beaten 
in many places. Indeed, everywhere the spirit of freedom 
was breaking through the heavy crust of the Middle Ages, 
and man was struggling to become a true individual and 
obtain some power to rule himself. 

Added to this was the growing feeling of nationalism 
evident on all sides. Groups of individuals with common 
language, customs, and traditions began to appear and to 
assert themselves over against other such groups. But there 
was opposition to all such nations on the part of the Church, 
which saw its world domination threatened. Thus, a strug- 
gle ensued out of which gradually developed the nations 
of the modern world, large groups of individuals with a 
common concern and a growing desire to establish them- 
selves as units. 

In addition, the individual began to assert his own inde- 
pendence of thought, and to believe that human reason 
was superior to authority. Slowly the idea took form that 
truth was a thing to be reached by the operation of human 
reason and not something handed down by an authorita- 
tive Church. 

All these movements tended to weaken the power of the 
Church and place the individual man, both as an individ- 
ual and as a member of a political group, in the center of 



MAN AND THE STA1K 193 

the stage. In this setting philosophers began to dream of a 
perfect social group in which, ideal conditions would exist. 
An example of this trend is the City of the Stm, a Utopian 
treatise by TOMMASO CAMPANEIXA. In this volume Cam- 
panella sketches the outline of a socialistic state similar 
to that found in Plato's Republic, a state in which knowl- 
edge is the governing force and power. Everyone in this 
state is equal since there is only one class. However, Cam- 
panella does make distinctions between men on the basis of 
their knowledge. The philosophers, who are also priests, 
are the rulers. In making this assertion, he shows his de- 
sire to effect a compromise between the Church and the 
growing national feeling of the times* In his state there 
was to be a sort of papal monarchy, a religious unity as the 
basis for political unity. 

Campanella's work is typical of the preliminary work 
toward thinking through a new theory of the state and its 
relations with, its citizens. However, the general trend of 
the times was away from the authority and dominance of 
the Church, a trend in the direction of political independ- 
ence. 

MachfaveTlfs Conception of the State 

The most violent attack upon the Church and its hitherto 
generally accepted dominance over the state was made by 
NiccoiA MAGHTAVEtxT. His ambition was to establish a 
united Italian nation wholly independent of the Church. 
He took as a model for this state the old political forms 
established by Sparta, Rome, and Venice. 

Since the general situation of his day was one of cor- 
ruption, Machiavelli argued that such a state could be 
established only by a strong and absolute despot. Although 
such a political structure would destroy civic freedom, 
Machiavelli thought of this as a necessary intermediate 
stage out of which man could eventually work as he be- 
came less corrupt His ideal was a free, independent na- 
tion in which civic rights would be cherished and the in- 
dependence of each individual guaranteed. 

To accomplish his ends, the prince or ruler had the right 



194 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHDLOSOPHEBS 

to use any means necessary, even force, deceit, or breach 
of the moral law. He had to fight trickery with trickery, 
deceit with deceit. 

Grotius, HoVbes, and Other Thinkers of the Renaissance 

Another thinker of the period, JEAN BODIN, taught that 
the state is founded upon a contract which the people make 
with their ruler. The fundamental article of this contract 
is one which gives over to the ruler aH authority and which 
permits the people under no circumstances to take it back. 

JOHANNES ALTHUSIUS attacked this position, holding that 
the people could never give away their authority. Rather, 
he argued, the contract which the people make with their 
ruler lasts only so long as the ruler fulfills his part of the 
bargain. When he violates the contract he may be de- 
throned and execrated and another ruler set up in his place 
by the people. 

HTJGO GROTTOS, a leader of the aristocratic party in Hol- 
land, developed the theory of absolutism in great detail 
and with many cogent arguments. He taught that man 
has certain natural rights which are rooted in his very 
nature and which even God cannot change or destroy. But 
these natural rights may be limited!, and indeed are limited 
by the positive law which results from man's voluntary 
agreement to live in groups. We give up the privilege to 
exercise certain natural rights in order that we may live 
together as members of a state. Thus, the state is a result 
of the free agreement among its members. Consequently, 
at no time can man give up his natural rights uncondi- 
tionally. But, he may delegate these rights to a ruler for- 
ever. 

Therefore, during this early modern period the tendency 
was toward absolutism. The ruler had power which, though 
originally given him by the people, was more or less ab- 
solute from then on. Of course, there was opposition to 
this point of view. When the practice of more or less ab- 
solute sovereignty reached its climax in the reign of Louis 
XIV in France, a climax expressed in his famous saying, 
"I am the state,** there was sufficient opposition to effect 



MAN AND THE STATE 195 

an overthrow of the whole position and to begin building 
the more modem idea of democracy. But that is getting 
ahead of our story. 

The materialist, THOMAS HOBBES, based his theory of 
the state upon the fundamental principle that rmm has 
the natural right to do anything which he pleases. The 
most primitive urge of all men is that of self-preservation. 
To accomplish this end, man may use any means he deems 
necessary. In this state of nature man may invade the 
rights of others with the result that chaos reigns. 

Man is, then, fundamentally a ferocious animal, one 
who engages in war and pillage, seeking always his own 
gain. But, in such a state no man can be strong enough to 
preserve himself for long. Each man will destroy the 
others and he in turn will be destroyed by others. Thus, to 
escape from this inevitable end, man creates a society in 
which he voluntarily gives up his rights in many matters. 
This is a contract which men make with each other by 
which they give up certain rights in order to obtain others 
which they desire. To insure this mutual contract, men 
transfer power to one ruler or an assembly. After the ruler 
has been set up and given power, men must obey. 

It is true, Hobbes recognizes, that at times the ruler will 
be unjust and will wreak hardships upon men. But they 
have no right to rebel. Hobbes justifies this position by 
holding that even at their worst, the injustices of a ruler 
are never so bad as the original state of man before power 
was given to the ruler. 

Hobbes believes that the absolute monarchy is the best 
form of government But, there are certain things that 
even the king cannot force men to do. Among these are 
suicide, murder, or the confession of crime. These the king 
has no right to impose upon any man. 

Hobbes argued further that the king was God's repre- 
sentative on earth and that God spoke through him. Thus, 
freedom of religion cannot be tolerated. The religion of the 
king must be the religion of all the people. 

This theory of Hobbes is actually an attempt to defend 



196 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

philosophically the power of the English king and the gen- 
eral structure of the English monarchy. The defense led to 
the theory of the "divine right of kings* and to the position 
that the king can do no wrong. So long as the king can 
protect the people he is absolute and no one has the right 
to challenge Tfo authority. 

The Views of Spinoza, Locke, and Adam Smith 

The belief that the state is in some way a result of a 
social contract among men is also seen in the teachings of 
SPINOZA, In the natural state, he held, might makes right, 
and man has the right to do anything which he is able to do. 
He may destroy others to gain his ends, cheat, lie, or en- 
gage in any activity which will help Mm. But, in such a 
state, conflict will inevitably arise and many will be de- 
stroyed* 

Consequently, men give up many natural rights so that 
there may be a degree of peace in which they can realize 
other desires. Hie state is the result By general agreement, 
men in a state agree to limit their natural rights for the 
good of aH Therefore, only in a state can justice and in- 
justice have a meaning. According to natural rights any- 
thing may be Just However, in a state, disobedience to 
the laws set up by virtue of the social contract is unjust 
The just is that which makes social life possible. 

JOHN LOCKE was in complete disagreement with Hobbes 
and others who believed that the natural state of man was 
one of war and self-seeking. Further, he was opposed to the 
doctrine that the king rules by divine right and that he 
has absolute power to govern men as he wills. Locke held 
that the original and natural state of all men is one of 
perfect freedom and equality. Since all men are free and 
equal, no one has the right to take away another's life, 
liberty, or possessions. 

Further, the original nature of man is that of peace, 
good will, and mutual assistance. Thus, men naturally 
move toward social living. In a society, men set up law, an 
impartial judge, and one with executive power in order to 
attend to matters of common interest This structure is 



MAN AND THE STATE 1Q7 

established by a social contract agreed upon by the mem- 
bers of the group. 

After the society has been established, each member is 
under obligation to submit to the authority of the majority. 
This is necessary for efficient living together, since unani- 
mous consent is next to impossible in a large group* 

The main purpose of law, Locke taught, is to preserve 
the social group and thus it must be limited to the public 
good of society. Beyond this, men are to be left free. 
Locke said that there are certain areas into which law 
cannot come. He specifically excluded the right to enslave, 
to destroy, or to impoverish men. 

Locke did not think it good that those who made the 
laws should also have the right to execute them. Conse- 
quently, he would divide the powers of government into 
the legislative and the executive and would keep these 
two branches separate for the public good The people 
have the power to remove the legislators whenever they 
wish since power rests ultimately in the people. They also 
have the right to punish their legislators or their executive 
whenever they are convinced that either is acting in oppo- 
sition to the public good. 

It is obvious that Hobbes and Locke were exponents of 
two very different doctrines. While Hobbes was interested 
in presenting a philosophical justification for absolute mon- 
archy and the divine right of the ruler to rule without be- 
ing accountable to the people, Locke was interested in 
justifying the doctrine of political freedom. Locke sought 
to prove that the power of the state always rests in the 
people and that their rulers are merely their servants sub- 
ject to their will. This power can never be taken from the 
people nor can they give it up. Hobbes held that once the 
people gave power to the ruler, they were unable to get 
it back regardless of what the ruler did. 

These were two points of view which appeared often in 
the political writings of the eighteenth century and the 
early part of the nineteenth century. They were in con- 
stant conflict, and the conflict has not died down even to- 
day. 

This theory as developed by Locke, a theory of man's 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHELOSOPHEES 

freedom and of the state as an institution charged with 
keeping order among men, but one very limited, led to 
the famous doctrine of laissez fairs. This is the doctrine 
that the state should not interfere any more than is ab- 
solutely necessary with the affairs of its members, that 
tie individual has a natural right to exercise his activity 
in the economic sphere with the least possible interference 
from society. 

ADAM SMTIH wrote Bis famous Wealth of Nations to 
show that the best state exists only when men are permitted 
to engage in unrestricted competition, freedom of ex- 
change, and enlightened self-interest In this work the 
pendulum of philosophic thought was swinging away from 
the theory that the state should regulate every activity of 
men, a theory held by Plato and many other thinkers, to 
the opposite extreme that the state should observe a strict 
policy of Bands off and permit men to exercise their natural 
rights in all directions save in those where the safety of 
fee group is threatened. 

In Adam Smith, and other philosophical writers wBo 
followed Locke, we see the attempt to carry Locke's theory 
of freedom and natural rights into various fields of human 
activity and to free men in each of these fields from the 
restraints of government which Bad become so common 
since the beginning of written Bistory at least. In most 
instances it was felt that the best results would be obtained 
if each individual was left as free as possible in all his 
activities. Government was to keep hands off except in 
those necessary affairs where the safety of the state was in 
danger* 

The Position of Voltaire and of Rousseau 

The brilliant VOLTAIBE never tired of condemning the 
traditional authorities and championing human freedom. 
Yet, he did not believe that the lower classes had the 
capacity for self-government. He believed that the "igno- 
rant rabble" was a danger whenever restraint was removed. 
Thus, freedom was to be the privilege only of the en- 
lightened, the intelligent 



MAN ANB THE STATE 199 

A powerful opponent of this position was JEAN JACQUES 
ROUSSEAU. He believed in all men and fought for their 
freedom. Indeed, he would rule out representative govern- 
ment and place in its stead direct government by all the 
people. The Swiss republic was his model, a small, closely- 
knit group of people considering every issue as a group and 
determining their destiny by popular vote. Indeed, Tlous- 
seau took the Lockian idea of democracy seriously" and 
argued that since all men were created free and equal they 
should not be robbed or ruled by a privileged class. 

To attain this freedom, Rousseau would cast away all 
the trappings of modern society and return to nature. Nat- 
ural society, he believed, is based on a "social contract" 
by which the freedom of the individual is surrendered to 
self-imposed laws which are the result of the general will. 
Sovereignty lies, he argued, with the people at all times and 
cannot be taken from them. Government merely carries 
out the will of the people, and the people have the right 
at any time to recall their government and establish an- 
other. 

Locke, Rousseau, Fichte, Schelling, and many other 
thinkers, although differing in some details, held the gen- 
eral position that man's true self could be realized only in 
the right land of a social group. They saw that human 
association is not a detriment but is rather a means to the 
best kind of life. When a man lives among his fellows he 
develops characteristics which are most worth while. There- 
fore, they sought the right kind of social group, and 
reached the conclusion that a group in which the greatest 
amount of freedom was possible would meet the require- 
ments of this society. Schelling argued that an isolated ego 
could have no consciousness of freedom. We only know 
freedom when we live with others and see it in relation to 
possible restraint. 

The State According to Hegel, Mart, and Lassd&e 

HEGEL taught that universal reason reaches its height 
in a society of free individuals, each subordinating its in- 
dividual reason to the universal reason. The individual, if 



BASIC CACHINGS OF GREAT I>HILOSOPHERS 

living by himself and exercising his own caprice, is not 
free. Only as He blends himself with, the group does he 
attain to true freedom* History, he held, has been striving 
throughout time toward the realization of a perfect state, 
a state in which each member so blends himself with the 
whole that the will of the whole is his will. 

For Hegel, there is a universal reason to be discovered 
throughout history. It is seen working itself out in one 
society and then shifting to another. Thus, when one society 
destroys or conquers another, the universal reason shifts to 
another group and continues to work itself out The con- 
queror becomes the agent of this universal reason. War, 
then, is justified ia Hegel's mind because it is the means by 
whidb progress is made. 

The Hegelian system was adopted by the Prussian state 
and many Prussian thinkers held that the Prussian state 
was destined to carry forward the realization of universal 
reason through its eventual conquest of the world. 

KAKL MAKX and FERDINAND LASSAUUS, along with other 
early socialists (founders of modern socialism), derived 
certain of their views from Hegel, especially his idea that 
change is but the road to better things. They held that one 
type of society, which appeared good at one time, would 
inevitably give way to another which would be seen to be 
better, a synthesis of opposites. Thus, for example, a so- 
ciety based on private property would give way to one in 
which socialism was supreme. They saw in Hegel a philo- 
sophical justification for the new society which they de- 
sired. 

De Maisfre, Saint-Simon, and Comte 

The result of the Lockian tradition of freedom and popu- 
lar sovereignty in France was the revolution and the ac- 
companying social and political upheaval. This inevitably 
gave impetus to a great deal of conservative reaction with 
its emphasis upon the need of authority, JOSEPH DE MAIS- 
TBE, for example, held that man had shown his inability 
to govern himself and argued that a stable society was 
possible only on the basis of tradition and strong authority. 



MAN AND THE STATO 2O1 

However, the desire for "liberty, equality, and fraternity** 
continued to burn brightly and the dream of reforming 
society haunted thinkers. They recognized that merely to 
proclaim freedom and equality was not enough, but that 
actual reforms of society were necessary. CLAUDE HENRI 
DE ROUVROY, COMTE BE SAINT-SIMON believed that the 
goal of freedom and equality could be reached if men 
could build a science of society based upon the laws of 
group living. Such a scientific society would elevate the 
poor and the lowly and would bring to the world true 
Christianity with its doctrine of love for the oppressed. In 
such a society there would be equal distribution of prop- 
erty, power, culture, and happiness. 

But Saint-Simon was not the thinker to develop this 
science of society. He could see the need for it and could 
preach this need, but it was left for a man of the intellec- 
tual strength of AUGDSTK COMTE to actually attempt the 
logical construction of such a positive philosophy. He saw 
that social reform was impossible without a knowledge of 
the laws of society, the development of a social science 
equal in logical accuracy to the other sciences of his time. 

Sociology, the science of society, Comte held to be the 
most complex of the sciences, including both an under- 
standing of society as it now is and also a study and under- 
standing of the progress of society. 

Comte held that society begins as a way to satisfy man's 
social impulse which is fundamental to him. As man pro- 
gresses, his social life passes through the three stages: mili- 
tarism, in which discipline and force are supreme; revolu- 
tion; and the positive stage, in which the emphasis is upon 
social rather than political problems. It is this positive stage 
in which the expert guides scientific research and controls 
all phases of living. This expert is not to be dependent 
upon the ignorant; therefore popular government is not 
desirable. 

The ideal of social living, the positive state, is for Comte 
one which has passed beyond the stage of chaos repre- 
sented by the revolutions which followed the Lockian in- 
fluence. Here the expert has emerged and is able through 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHEBS 

the strength of his ability to direct society toward more and 
more perfect living. He sees the needed reforms of society 
and is able to effect them. The masses of men accept his 
guidance because he is an expert 

The Views of Mill and Spencer 

This dream of social reform and the building of a more 
ideal society was basic to the thinking of JOHN STUABT 
MILL also. He believed that the phenomena of social living 
conformed to fixed laws fust as other phenomena do. How- 
ever, he recognized that the factors involved in society are 
so numerous and are changing so constantly that prediction 
is impossible, Thus, the methods of study used in other 
sciences, those of the laboratory, are not applicable to a 
study of society* By the method of deduction from many 
instances we can see tendencies in human social develop- 
ment and can point to them as guides to activity, he taught. 

Believing this to be true, Mill held that the task of the 
social scientists was to investigate social groups to discover 
how the different forms of society develop and follow each 
other. Thus, by a study of history we can discover the laws 
of social progress and development Then we can point to 
tendencies in the present social structure and predict that 
there is a high degree of probability tibat certain social 
results can be expected. 

For example, a study of ancient civilizations will show 
the reasons for their fall. The historian can point to factors 
m the social structure which contributed to the downfall 
of the civilization. Then, if an examination of a present 
society reveals the same factors as present and operating, 
it can be predicted with a degree of probability that that 
society will also fall* 

Mill, as many of his predecessors, recognized that 
social well-being was necessary for individual well-being, 
that the individual was tied up with the group and that 
his happiness was dependent upon the status of the group. 
Thus, he dreamed of a society in which the happiness and 
prosperity of all was certain, and in which all would share 
the wealth of the group. In his Autobiography he wrote, 



MAN AND THE STATE 

**Whfle we repudiated with the greatest energy that tyr- 
anny of society over the individual which most Socialistic 
systems are supposed to involve, we yet looked forward to 
a time when society will no longer be divided into the idle 
and the industrious; when the rule that they who do not 
work shaTT not eat wiH be applied not to paupers only, but 
impartially to al; when the division of the produce of labor, 
instead of depending, as in so great a degree it now does, on 
the accident of birth, will be made by concert on an ac- 
knowledged principle of justice; and when it wifl no longer 
either be, or be thought to be, impossible for human beings 
to exert themselves strenuously in procuring benefits which 
are not to be exclusively their own, but to be shared with 
the society they belong to. The social problem of the future, 
we considered to be: how to unite the greatest individual 
liberty of action, with a common ownership in the raw 
material of the globe, and an equal participation of all in 
the benefits of combined labor." 

Mill was struggling here with a problem that seems to 
have become more and more clear since his day: the prob- 
lem of undeserved poverty and equally undeserved wealth, 
Society, as he understood it, exists for the good of all in- 
dividual members. Therefore, each must have freedom to 
work and be rewarded for his effort But, the raw ma- 
terials of the world cannot be the exclusive possession of a 
few. These belong to aH, and must be held by society as the 
representative of afl. Mffl believed that a time would come 
when such would be the case and when society could 
guarantee economic freedom to all 

HEBBERT SPENCER accepted the doctrine that each in- 
dividual had the right to preserve himself. Indeed, he saw 
in nature a struggle in which the fittest survived and the 
less fit perished. Thus, men must be free to struggle and 
prove their fitness to survive. 

But; the survival of the fittest among human individuals 
depends, he argued, upon group life. Isolated from his fel- 
lows, even the fittest o men, would parish. Therefore so- 
ciety is essential. This necessitates a course of activity in 
which each individual is restricted by the rights of others. 



2O4 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

One may do what he wills in this struggle, but he must not 
violate the freedom of others. Everyone has the right to 
act to a certain limit, but no further. 

However, Spencer would not accept the socialistic thesis 
of Mill. For him, the state is greatly restricted. Its chief 
functions are to prevent internal aggression and to protect 
its members from foreign invasion. Beyond this it cannot 
go. To own the raw materials of the world and distribute 
them for the good of all was not a function of the state, 
to his thinking. In this direction he saw only danger, the 
danger of complete state control and the inevitable sup- 
pression of the individual. 

Competition among the members of society was to be 
permitted and encouraged. He believed that society, and 
the welfare of each individual, was better served by the es- 
tablishment of as few restrictions upon competition as pos- 
sible. In this, Spencer was an advocate of the laissez-faire 
theory. The best life, he taught, was one lived with only a 
minimum of regulation by the state. 

Nietzsche s Conception of the State 

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE had no use for equality or any- 
thing that suggested democracy. The will to power is his 
dominant idea. In the struggle of the universe, this will to 
power is expressed; and the most powerful wins and has the 
right to win. If others are weaker and are unable to survive, 
that is good. The weak should be destroyed anyhow to 
make room for the strong. 

He recognizes differences among men and believes that 
these differences should be magnified. The more powerful 
should rule, and the weaker should be ruled. Slavery seems 
perfectly natural to him; and he feels that women, being 
weaker than men, cannot be expected to have the same 
rights as men. Thus, he repudiates all that has been held 
by that long line of philosophers whose constant theme 
has been the equality of all men and the right of all to share 
equally in the goods of society. For Nietzsche, society is 
merely a field in which the strong have a chance to demon- 
strate their strength and win their rewards, while the weak 



MAN AND THE STATE 

are defeated and dragged from the arena to be disposed of 
completely. Since inequality is characteristic of nature and 
the natural state of man, it is unnatural to replace it with a 
forced equality. 

The Views of Dewey and Recent Thinkers 

JOHN DEWEY has shown at all times a strong interest in 
society and its problems. He constantly attempts to inter- 
pret the modern democratic point of view, to reveal its 
implications, and to forecast its future. He thinks of society, 
at its best, as a group of individuals sharing their experi- 
ences and growing through this sharing. The individual is 
to be free, but this freedom is not to be that of the older 
tradition. As the individual becomes a true member of so- 
ciety he is incorporated into the group in such a way that 
he can contribute to the welfare of the whole and receive 
from the whole that which makes him truly human. 

At all times Dewey recognizes the importance of the in- 
dividual. He holds that no one should ever be treated as an 
instrument, as a means to some goal that is not his. Rather, 
each one should be treated as an end in himself. ^Respect 
for human personality" is the chief doctrine of his philoso- 
phy. This is, perhaps, the only absolute known to Dewey 
and his school of thought. 

Man, Dewey holds, is man because he lives in society. 
To the extent that his activities in the group lead on to 
richer and more rewarding activities for him and for all 
members of the group, he is acting wisely and truly. So- 
ciety, group fife, is the way to this complete and full life 
since here mutual sharing is possible. 

Thus, we may say that two points of view are basic to 
the great mass of recent writing which deals with matters 
of the state. On the one hand are those who follow more or 
less completely the lead of men from Plato to Nietzsche 
and hold that inequality is the natural state of man. This 
being the case, each member of the state must take his 
proper place in the social structure. It is perfectly right and 
natural, these men argue, that some should be rulers and 
others should be ruled, and the ruled should not question 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT FHELOSOPHEBS 

the acts of the rulers. Such writers spurn democracy, so- 
cialism, and all other systems of human equality and free- 
dom. Plato saw democracy as the open door to anarchy. 
He would have the philosopher-king rule, and all others 
take their places in a tightly organized system. 

Hegel carried this idea one step further when he held 
that certain states or groups of individuals were by nature 
superior to others and therefore should rule them. This, of 
course, is the basic point of view of all totalitarian systems 
of government. 

Opposed to this entire trend is the democratic tradition 
which grew out of the Renaissance and came to fruition 
in the work of men like Locke, Rousseau, and their f ol- 
lowers. It holds that all men are by nature free and equal. 
This position is basic to the French Revolution and the 
American Declaration of Independence and Constitution. It 
affirms that there are certain rights with which all men 
are endowed by their Creator, and which cannot be taken 
away from them under any conditions. These rights have 
been listed in many ways, chief of which is life, liberty, 
and the pursuit of happiness.** 

This position led to the influential doctrine of laissez 
faire, a doctrine which characterized the early years of 
development in the United States. It limited the authority 
of the state and magnified the freedom of the individual to 
work and hold the rewards of his work. 

Today philosophers are seeking to discover a balance be- 
tween these two positions. Complete freedom leads to a 
crass individualism in which the powerful oppress the weak. 
Complete regulation leads to the same end, but the oppres- 
sors are those who happen to gain control of the govern- 
ment. Dewey and many modem thinkers agree in this 
seeks a freedom within the social group by which both the 
individual and the group will prosper* A great many of the 
social experiments of the present are in this direction, seek- 
ing to balance individual interests and group interests in 
such a way that both will be served and neither sacrificed 
to the other. 



Chapter VIII 
MAN AND EDUCATION 

THE SOPHISTS PLATO ARISTOTLE QUINTTLIAN 
ABELARD LUTHER BACON HOBBES 

COMENIUS LOCKE ROUSSEAU 
PESTALOZZI HERBART FROEBEL BEWEY 



Why do we establish schools and pay for tliem? Is the 
fundamental purpose of education the training of obe- 
dient citizens of a totalitarian state, or is U the devel- 
opment of free men in a democracy? Shall the church 
or the state dominate the schools? What shall we 
teach in our schools? 



As we survey the whole course of man's development 
from the earliest times to the present and from the most 
primitive and simple to the most complex ways of living, 
we are strongly impressed by the fact that wherever men 
have lived together there has been some group interest in 
education. As the group becomes more complex this in- 
terest grows, and institutions definitely charged with the 
task of teaching are created. Thus the school comes into 
existence and an educational system evolves. 

But, so far as we know from the meager records which 
have been left, early man had only a very simple educa- 
tional system. Most of the child's learning was picked up 
as he associated with his parents and other members of the 
family, tribe, dan, or larger group. He learned to fish and 
hunt, to prepare his food, to fight his enemies, and to take 



208 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

care of his simple and elementary needs. In short, he 
learned to survive in the world in which he found himself. 

In time, however, as traditions and customs grew, this 
simple association together was not enough* The child 
could not learn all that was necessary by this method. As 
a result the older men of the group took it upon themselves 
to instruct the young at certain times in traditions, customs, 
and group lore. One of the most important of these times 
was the age of puberty, when the child was initiated into 
the group as an adult Special initiation rites were held, and 
if the young man stood the tests imposed upon him he was 
told the most cherished secrets of the group and then ac- 
cepted by the group as a full member. Thus education be- 
came a definite concern of the group. 

As the life of the group became more complex, certain 
members of the group took it upon themselves to become 
thoroughly familiar with the traditions and the customs 
and devoted most of their time to the teaching of the 
young. At first, this teaching was done wherever the 
teacher and a group of learners cared to gather. But later 
specified places for teaching and learning were set up. 
These were the first schools. 

Often these places of teaching and learning were also 
the places where members of the group gathered for re- 
ligious purposes. This was due to the fact that among 
early people the traditions, customs, lore, and ways of 
living were tied up closely with their religion. Their gods 
were believed to be the powers who established customs 
and traditions. Thus, worship of the gods and compliance 
with customs and traditions were so closely united that 
education was largely religious education, and everything 
that was learned had a religious sanction. Consequently, it 
was natural that the teachers should be men of religious 
power and that the places of learning should be also the 
places of worship. 

The ancient Hebrews reveal this fact clearly. Their 
schools were held in the synagogue or place of religious 
worship and their teachers were the rabbis. Even though 
education kter became concerned with a great deal more 



MAN AND EDUCATION 2OQ 

than mere religious matters, the leaders of the religious 
life of the poeple continued to hold a dominant position in 
the education of the young, and a large part of the material 
taught was directly or indirectly of a religious nature. 

In time the thinkers or philosophers began to devote con- 
siderable attention to the matter of education. They 
wanted to know what should be taught the young and 
how it should be taught They gave thought to the rela- 
tionship of education to the rest of group life, its impor- 
tance and necessity. They took up questions of the aims 
or purposes of education, of the methods of teaching, of 
what should be taught In this way education became a 
major concern of the philosophers. 

This development was logical and necessary. If a philoso- 
pher believed that a certain thing was true, his next ques- 
tion was: How can others be instructed so as to believe it 
to be true? Every philosopher, as soon as he developed his 
philosophy, was confronted with the problem of how to 
get others to accept his philosophy as true. And the an- 
swer was always "through education." 

Education as Viewed by the Early Greek Philosophers 

Among the Greeks, the Sophists, as we have seen, were 
individualists. They believed that man should be trained 
to take care of himself at all times and advance himself in 
his community at all cost. Thus, they advocated a system 
of education which would promote the happiness and in- 
sure the success of the individual. Since a great deal of 
man's activity at that time hinged upon public discus- 
sion and the workings of public opinion, the Sophists based 
their education upon training in debate and oratory. They 
wanted the young men trained to argue well and con- 
vincingly before their fellows so that they might win their 
cases. 

This training was careful and thorough. The young men 
learned to build logical arguments which could not be 
broken down, and to deliver these arguments with a per- 
suasiveness of voice and personality such as to win their 
hearers. This included training in logic, mastery of the 



210 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

laws and customs of the Athenians, a familiarity with the 
literature of the past so as to be able to use illustrations 
from it, great practice in speaking and careful training 
of the voice, and a thorough mastery of the language of 
the people so that it could be used with ease and brilliance. 
The Sophists, strolling teachers who taught for a fee, held 
that an individual so trained could rise to high places in 
the life of Athens and could lead the people. But, there 
was tied up with this a belief on the part of many Sophists 
that the best speaker should also be the best man. PRO- 
TAGOHAS is believed to have said, *If you associate with me, 
on that very day you will return a better man than you 
came.** Part of the work of fitting a young man for a 
successful career, as many Sophists saw, consisted in mak- 
ing him a better -man in every way. 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 

SOCRATES, although disagreeing with the Sophists in 
many respects, held this same general belief. He stated 
that education should make a man a better citizen and 
thereby a happier individual. However, while the Sophists 
placed emphasis upon the individual man, Socrates em- 
phasized man as a member of the group. He taught that 
the most valuable thing a man could have was knowledge* 
and that such knowledge was to be obtained by removing 
individual differences and discovering the essentials upon 
which all men would agree. 

This belief lead Socrates to go about Athens challenging 
the statements and beliefs of those with whom he spoke. 
He would show that many beliefs were false because they 
were superficial. Then he would continue the discussion 
by probing the topic deeply until he discovered the es- 
sential truth about it His method has become known as 
the ^dialectic* or "Socratic" method. It consists of taking a 
statement made by another and so analyzing it as to re- 
veal its inconsistencies. Then, after the other person rec- 
ognizes the fallacies in his view, the questioner asks him 
a series of questions in which he brings out what he be- 
lieves to be the truth. 



MAH AND EDUCATION 

Socrates was a great teacher, who devoted Mm self to 
the practice of education. His pupil, PLATO, developed 
one of the first theories of education. In the Republic, one 
of Plato's great works, we find a system of education which, 
Plato believed, would insure a happy and just state. 

Since Plato believed that men were by nature different 
and should be put into classes corresponding with their 
basic differences, he developed a plan of education which 
would meet this need It was a plan by which men would 
be selected and trained for work in one of three classes. 
During the first eighteen years of a boy's life he was to be 
trained in gymnastics, music, and literature, learning to 
read and write, to pky and sing, and to take part in many 
sports. At eighteen those boys who showed ability were 
given further training, while the rest stopped and became 
tradesmen, merchants, and the like* 

Those boys who were retained in the educational system 
were given two years of cadet training. At twenty, those 
who were found to be incapable of going on were put into 
the military class and charged with defending the country. 
The remainder were given more extensive training in phi- 
losophy, mathematics, music, science, and other cultural 
subjects, and would eventually become the leaders of so- 
ciety. 

In this system Plato was endeavoring to use education to 
pick men for the various duties of a social group. In each 
case, however, he sought to pick men in terms of their 
abilities as discovered by a system of education. It is evi- 
dent that Plato held education to be a matter erf state con- 
cern. It was supported and controlled by the state and its 
function was to select and train men for service in the 
state. Plato believed that if the state would adopt this sys- 
tem of education, it would produce an ideal society in 
which everyone would be doing the work for which he was 
suited and trained and thus would be happy. 

ABISTOTLE held that the aim of education should be to 
make people virtuous. Thus, there should be three periods 
of training fitted to the three periods in the development 
of an individual The first period, from birth to seven years 



212 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

of age, should be concerned wholly with the training of 
the body in preparation for formal schooling. The second 
period would be that of formal schooling, from seven to 
twenty-one years of age. This would consist of training in 
literature, music, gymnastics, and the like. 

For Aristotle, as for Plato, education was a state matter 
and should be controlled by the state. Aristotle would have 
the state determine what children should live and what 
ones should be destroyed soon after birth because of phys- 
ical deformities. Further, he would have the state deter- 
mine whom a man should marry, so that desirable off- 
spring would be assured. The state, he held, should use 
education in order to develop citizens who could defend the 
state and make it better. 

The positions taken by Plato and Aristotle, positions em- 
phasizing the use of education by the state as a means for 
training good citizens, did not have wide influence in the 
life of Athens in their day. Rather, the Sophist position 
that education was for individual interests dominated. The 
individualism of the times was not to be suppressed by a 
few philosophers. The people listened to the philosophers, 
but they followed their own interests and demanded a type 
of education which would make them most successful and 
happy. They were carried away with visions of personal 
success and individual happiness and were in no mood to 
listen to philosophers who suggested that both success and 
happiness in the long run depended upon the welfare of 
the group. 

The Roman Conception of Education 

In Rome, education followed the pattern which had been 
developed by the Sophists. The ideal of the Roman was 
the orator who could sway the multitudes with his elo- 
quence. Success in public life was largely determined by 
the power which one possessed to speak in public and to 
influence mass opinion. QUJLNTJULIAN, the Roman authority 
on education, pointed out that tie orator had to be more 
than an eloquent speaker. He must also be "a good man/* 
one of "excellent mind." He believed that "the man who 



MAN AND EDUCATION 213 

can duly sustain his character as a citizen, who is qualified 
for the management of public and private affairs, and who 
can govern communities by his counsels, settle them by 
means of laws, and improve them by means of judicial en- 
actments, can certainly be nothing else but an orator." 

Thus, tie heart of Roman education was the training of 
the orator. This included knowledge of logic, good morals, 
a careful schooling in the laws of the nation, and a char- 
acter that was above suspicion. CICERO developed this 
scheme thoroughly and became himself the model of the 
Roman orator. 

Early Christian Conception of Education 

With the development of Christianity education was 
once more concerned with religious questions. Those in- 
dividuals who wished to become members of the Christian 
community needed instruction in the beliefs and rites of 
the Christian faith. Thus "catechumenaT schook were es- 
tablished to give such instruction to the "catechumens'* or 
candidates for admission to the group. Further, as Chris- 
tianity came into contact with other religions and the phi- 
losophies of the world it became necessary to train leaders 
who could explain Christian beliefs to the leaders and the 
people of the times. This led to the setting up of "catecheti- 
cal" schools in which instruction was carried on by the 
question and answer method, the method of the catechism. 
Out of these schools came the Apologists, men able to meet 
the questionings of those interested in Christianity and to 
answer the many critics of the movement. Many of these 
Apologists, after receiving training in the catechetical 
schools, became teachers in them and instructed a great 
number of individuals who spread throughout the then- 
known world preaching and teaching the Christian beliefs 
and doctrines. Among the most important of these were 
CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA and the great theologian 
ORIGEN. 

These men, along with many others, believed in educa- 
tion as the only sure means of protecting the Christian 
movement and spreading .it throughout the world. For 



214 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

them education was not an instrument for the state, as 
Plato and Aristotle had held, but an instrument for the 
church, to be used in the service o God. The influence of 
these early Christian thinkers was wide, and schools under 
the control and direction of the church began to spring up 
everywhere. By 529 this movement had become so power- 
ful that the Emperor Justinian ordered all pagan schools 
dosed and permitted only Christian schools to operate. 
Thereby Christian education, a system under the control of 
the church, was left without a rival in the vast Roman 
Empire. 

St. Benedict and the Monastic Way of Life 

As life in the Roman Empire became more and more 
corrupt, many devout people fled from society and estab- 
lished themselves in secluded groups, living in monasteries. 
We speak of this way of life as "monasticism." Although 
the chief purpose of the various monasteries was religious 
living, education was not neglected. SAINT BENEDICT, head 
of the famous monastery at Monte Cassino in southern 
Italy, established a "rule 7 * for the government of the mem- 
bers of his monastery. This included work and study, and 
emphasized the belief that education was necessary for the 
continuance of Christianity. As the influence of Saint Bene- 
dict spread and his "rule" was adopted in principle by 
other monasteries, schools became a part of monastic life. 
At first these schools were devoted to the education of 
young men who planned to enter the monastery. Later 
others who wished some education but did not intend to 
devote themselves to the religious life came to the mon- 
asteries for training. Thus, two types of schools developed 
in connection with the monasteries, one for the "internT 
or those who were dedicated to religion and the other for 
the "externf* or those who came only for education. 

At first this education consisted merely of reading in or- 
der to study the Bible, writing to copy the sacred books, 
and some calculation for the figuring of holy days and other 
church festivals. By the end of the sixth century it had 
grown until it covered the "seven liberal arts" of grammar, 



MAN AND EDUCATION 215 

rhetoric, dialectic, arithmetic, geometry, music, and as- 
tronomy. These subjects were taught almost wholly by the 
question-and-answer method. 

Thus, throughout the so-called Dark Ages of European 
history, those centuries when the lamp of civilization 
burned low in Europe, some learning was preserved in the 
monasteries, a learning which was wholly under the control 
of and for the service of the church. Its flfoi was funda- 
mentally the salvation of the human soul in a world of 
temptation and sin. This became the general gfrn of all 
education during these dark days. 

Education in the Middle Ages and Early Renaissance 

A light in these centuries of darkness was the work of 
Charlemagne, Emperor of the Holy Roman Empire during 
the early part of the ninth century. He called the Anglo- 
Saxon ALCUIN from the monastic school at York, England, 
to help him establish a palace school and to reform edu- 
cation in his empire. Alcuin established a monastic school 
at Tours, and wrote many textbooks on grammar, rhetoric, 
and dialectic as well as a work on psychology. 

Alcuin had great influence in the empire and left his im- 
print upon many scholars, among them JOHN SCOTUS 
ERIGENA. Erigena and the others of this group followed 
the general position of the times in holding that education 
was fundamentally a matter of religion and the salvation 
of the human soul. Its purpose was vocational only in so 
far as it might serve to train young men for the church. 
Popular education was to be based wholly on religious mat- 
ters and everything taught pointed to religion in some way 
or other. This position, of course, helped the church to 
maintain itself as the dominant institution of these ages. 

The education of Scholasticism did not depart from this 
general point of view. Although the Schoolmen studied 
widely, their aim was to prove the reasonableness of the 
doctrines of the church. PETER ABELARD, one of the great- 
est of the Schoolmen, devoted much of his time to teach- 
ing and was influential in the founding of the University of 
Paris. Here theology was the dominant interest, and the 



2l6 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PfflLOSOPHEKS 

core of teaching was the presentation of the doctrines of 
the church. Abelard never lost the conviction that all the 
doctrines of the church could be proved to be logical and 
scientific. 

After several centuries, as we have seen, thinkers began 
to question tfrfc complete dominance of the church. It was 
inevitable, when men began to attempt to prove the doc- 
trines of the church by reasonable means, that some would 
question the proofs offered. 

Further, there began to arise classes of merchants and 
skilled tradesmen whose interests were largely outside of 
the church. They desired an education which would fit 
their children to follow them in their trades or to succeed 
in commercial pursuits. As these skilled workmen began to 
"unite into "guilds* or early trade unions, they established 
schools to train young men for service in the particular 
trades. In this way, guild schools and later burgher or town 
schools sprang Tip. Although religious questions were con- 
sidered in these schools, the main purpose for them was 
vocational rather than religious. 

Thus, as the Middle Ages faded so faded the complete 
dominance of the church in matters of education. Along 
with the guild and burgher schools there arose court 
schools founded and supported by wealthy rulers of the 
Italian cities. One of the most famous and influential of 
these was presided over by the noted scholar VITTOBINO 
DA FELTKE at Mantua. He sought a harmonious develop- 
ment of mind, body, and morals, following the teachings of 
the ancient Greeks. He wished to prepare boys for a prac- 
tical life in the world of the age. He gave time to Latin, 
mathematics, fencing, wrestling, dancing, ball-playing and 
other physical exercise, and also to the Latin and Greek 
classics which had been rediscovered by such men as 
Petrarch and his contemporaries. 

Schools similar to that of Vittorino were founded at 
Florence, Padua, Pavia, Milan, Ferrara, and other Italian 
cities. They all represented a move away from the church 
and a definite challenge to the religious dominance of edu- 
cation. 



MAN AND EDUCATION 



Martin Luther and the Protestant Reformation 

While the leaders of the Italian Renaissance were chal- 
lenging the church's control of education, the leaders of 
the Northern or German Renaissance were substituting. the 
control of the people's church, the Lutheran church, for 
that of the Roman Catholic church. MABTIN LUTHER, 
spearhead of the Protestant Reformation, the northern 
counterpart of the Italian Renaissance, held that everyone 
should know how to read his Bible and interpret it ac- 
cording to his understanding. 

Thus, Luther and his followers were driven by a neces- 
sary logic to support education for all people. They advo- 
cated training in the elements of reading, writing, and 
figuring, and held that, though fundamentally this knowl- 
edge was to make possible their understanding of the 
Bible and religion, it was also necessary for good citizen- 
ship. Luther wrote that even though there were no heaven 
nor hell, education would be necessary for the citizen, 

This swing away from the dominance of education by 
the church, and its control more and more by secular 
forces, led to the establishment of schools and school sys- 
tems by cities and by interested private groups. An ex- 
ample was the school of JOHANN STURM at Strassburg, 
which was then in Germany. This institution aimed at 
"piety, knowledge, and eloquence." Although religion was 
a prominent factor in the teaching of the school, other 
matters were also considered, and the control of the school 
was not in the hands of the church. 

As this trend toward secular education grew in strength 
there began to appear men who attempted to put it into 
philosophic form, to draw up a philosophy of education 
to fit the new age and new demands. JOHN MILTON, the 
great English poet, who was also a schoolmaster, urged 
students to turn to the ancient writings of Greece and 
Rome and study them, not for their form, but because they 
contained all that man needed for a happy life. He be- 
lieved that the best possible education was to be obtained 
from the study of these classical writings, 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

The Views of Bacon and Hobbes 

But tills devotion to the past did not hold Its own in the 
face o the growing interest in the world in which men 
were then living. Science was making itself known and 
respected. Men everywhere saw the value of scientific 
understanding and began to emphasize the need for scien- 
tific knowledge. Thus any philosophy of education which 
would prove acceptable to the age had to be based on the 
scientific knowledge then available. 

FRANCIS BACON pointed out the need for clear and ac- 
curate thinking, showing that any mastery of the world in 
which man lived was dependent upon careful understand- 
ing of the facts of this world. Bacon would first rid the 
mind of aH prejudices. Then he would have one observe 
carefully and collect all possible data from which to draw 
condusions or hypotheses to be tested by other data which 
could be collected later. As society accumulated more 
knowledge it should pass this on to the young through 
schools so that they would start in their thinking where 
their parents and the older members of society left off. 
Thus, education was, for him, a passing on of the knowl- 
edge of the past, the accumulated knowledge of society, to 
the young. 

The interest of THOMAS HOBBES in government led him 
to argue that the ruler should have the right to determine 
the kind of education fit for his subjects; and that the sub- 
jects must accept the educational system set up by the 
ruler. Education, according to Hobbes, is one of the ab- 
solute rights of the sovereign power. It serves to strengthen 
the state, and therefore should be watched carefully and 
controlled at all times. Here we have education as an in- 
strument of the state, set up and controlled to serve the 
ruler and his system. Each child should be trained in order 
to serve the state better. 

Comenius* Philosophy of Education 

Among the great educators of this period was JOHN 
AMOS COMENIXJS, a Moravian bishop and teacher. He be- 



MAN AND EDUCATION 

lieved that it was possible for everyone to learn everything. 
Thus he visioned a long period of encyclopedic training 
during which the student would be introduced to all sci- 
entific knowledge. At first everything was to be taught in 
*a general and undefined manner," while, as the child 
grew, teaching was to become more exact and specific. 
This training, Comenius argued, should follow the 
^method of nature. 3 * His plan was to expose the pupil to the 
world in which he lived, let him observe, and thereby lead 
fri to an understanding of things about him. As the child 
grew older his observations would become more detailed 
and cover a wider and wider area. 

Locke and "Rousseau 

Although the scientific trend in education, as developed 
by Bacon, Hobbes, and Comenius, interested him, JOHN 
LOCKE was more interested in the training of the English 
gentleman, a youth of breeding and wisdom. He con- 
demned the education of his day as being little more than 
a reproduction of the old interest in the classics and re- 
ligion. He did not believe that such would fit a man for the 
manifold duties of the world in which he lived. Conse- 
quently, Locke sought a more practical and efficient type 
of education. 

Locke held that the human soul at birth was a blank 
tablet but possessed of the power to receive impressions 
from the outside world and endowed with a desire for 
pleasure. Consequently, he saw education as the process of 
learning through experience with this outside world and 
working toward the realization of happiness. His ideal 
was a sound mind in a sound body. 

To realize this ideal, Locke advocated much physical 
exercise and a hardening process by which the body would 
become strong and able to endure hardships and long 
physical strain without breaking. Further, the child should 
be exposed to as much of the world about him as possible, 
so that he could receive impressions in great numbers. 
Travel, teaching by private tutors, and wide experience in 



22O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

the social world were advocated by Locke as methods for 
training. 

The aim of education, Loclce argued, should be an in- 
dividual who knew all the proper methods of association 
with his fellows, who was wise in the ways of the world so 
that he could take care of himself at all times, who was 
pious, and who had enough knowledge to meet the de- 
mands of his environment. This, of course, was a practical 
education which would fit the young man for complete 
living in the world of Locke's day. 

In contrast to this social emphasis in education, JEAN 
JACQUES ROUSSEAU held that society warps the child and 
that its influence is wholly evil. Consequently, he would 
protect the child from society at all times until he is so 
completely developed that society cannot destroy his inner 
nature. 

In his famous book, Emile, Rousseau outlines the edu- 
cation of a boy in a manner which is natural and sponta- 
neous. Emile, the hero of the story, is to be permitted to 
develop in accord with his own nature, without interfer- 
ence. Education is protective, a means of shielding the 
child from the influence of society which will warp the 
natural growth of his real self. 

For the first four years of the child's life, Rousseau 
would emphasize physical training, the development of 
the Ixxly. Then, from five to twelve years, the child would 
develop his senses. He would live in the world of nature, 
and observe many things. Intellectual training, through 
books and the like, would begin when the child is thirteen 
years old. Even here Rousseau would follow the natural 
curiosity of the child, and give instruction only as the 
child naturally came to demand it During this period the 
child would learn a trade in order to be economically inde- 
pendent. Between fifteen and twenty the child would be 
given moral training. Here he would come into contact 
with his fellows and learn the basic principles of sym- 
pathy, goodness, and service to mankind. Here religion 
would come into the picture. 

Although Rousseau emphasized the natural training of 



MAN AN1> EDUCATION 

boys, He did not believe that the same training should be 
given to girls. They should be educated to serve men and 
make them happy. Girls were to be fitted into a pattern 
demanded of men, one of restraint, While the boy should 
be free to develop according to bis own inner nature, the 
girl should be moulded to fit the pattern demanded by 
the man. 

Rousseau voiced the growing belief of his day that life 
should be freed from the many restraints which had been 
put about it. Men were breaking away from the past with 
all its hindrances. They had escaped from the dominance 
of the church, but found themselves dominated by the 
restraints of society. Hobbes* point of view, that the ruler 
as representative of society should set up an educational 
system which would make the young worthy citizens, was 
not acceptable to many. They felt that this system warped 
the original nature of man. Thus Rousseau said and wrote 
what was in the minds of many of his fellows. They wanted 
to free themselves not only from the church, but from 
the many requirements of society. Freedom was their 
watchword. 

JOHANN BEBNHABD BASEDOW came under the influence 
of Rousseau and established an educational institution in 
which he sought to put Rousseau's ideas into actual teach- 
ing. His school emphasized conversation and play. The 
interests of the child were considered so that this school 
became in a large measure a "child centered 7 * school. All 
instruction began with those things in which the child was 
interested, and moved along as interests grew. The idea 
spread, and many other educators sought to incorporate 
Rousseau's ideas into their teaching. 

Pestalozzfs Conception of Education 

One of the most influential educators to be influenced by 
Rousseau was JOHANN HEINBICH PESTAIXXZZI. He sought 
to understand the nature of children and to build his teach- 
ing on the "natural, progressive, and harmonious develop- 
ment of all the powers and capacities of the human being.* 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

As he understood the natural laws, he sought to develop 
children in accord with them. 

Thus some educators supported one and others sup- 
ported the other of two fundamental principles the prin- 
ciples of social control and of nature. Which should be 
dominant? Should education be a matter of building citi- 
zens according to a socially accepted and determined pat- 
tern, or should it be a following of the inner nature of the 
diild? Here, from another angle of course, is the old prob- 
lem of the individual and the group. Which should domi- 
nate? This was the problem of the eighteenth century, a 
century in which more and more emphasis was being 
placed upon the individual and his freedom, in which the 
ideas of freedom were being realized in the French and 
the American revolutions. 

JOHANN GOCTUEB FiCHTB approached education from 
the point of view of the state. In one of the darkest mo- 
ments in the life of the Prussian state he arose to deliver his 
famous Addresses to the German Nation. In these he ar- 
gued for group unity and social solidarity such as to create 
a new and strong nation. And, as a basis for this unity he 
advocated a strong system of education which would 
mould the people into a whole. Education, for hm^ was to 
be a means for building a nation. 

Thus, education should concern itself with the greatness 
of the nation. In a sense, it should be a program by which 
the people of the nation should come to know and love 
those factors of national life which were significant. Edu- 
cation, Fichte believed, was necessary to national unity 
and national progress. 

Herbert's View of Education 

Another great educational mind of this period was JO- 
HANN FRIEDRICH HEBBABT. His interest was fundamen- 
tally psychological, and this interest colored his thinking on 
educational matters. Experience, for him, is the sole source 
of knowledge. The mind receives impressions and organizes 
them. Then its further reception and use of impressions are 



MAN AND EDUCATION" 223 

determined by the impressions already received and or- 
ganized. 

Thus, the environment ia which the child is placed is of 
greatest importance. From this he receives his impressions. 
If it is good, his impressions will he good and he will be 
morally sound. Consequently, Herbart emphasized the 
place of the teacher in the educational system. It is the 
teacher who, to a great extent, determines what impres- 
sions the child receives. If the teacher is wise and clever, 
he will so set the scene that the child receives right im- 
pressions and will thereby develop a character which is 
good. 

FroebeTs Conception of Education 

Without doubt, one of the most consistent followers of 
Rousseau's ideas of naturalism in education was FKTEDEICH 
WILBELM AUGUST FEOEBEL. He believed firmly that the 
nature of the child was good and that it should be al- 
lowed to grow naturally. Education for him was a process 
of permitting and maldng possible this natural growth of 
the child. He called his school the Kindergarten, the gar- 
den of children. For him the school was to be operated as 
one might operate a garden. The teacher should permit 
and help the children to grow, just as the gardener helps 
the flowers to grow. 

However, Froebel went further than Rousseau did, in 
that he attempted to take into account the fact that the 
child is not merely an individual, but is also a member of a 
group. He would not shield the child from society, but 
would help him to adjust himself to society in such a way 
that his social and individual experiences would both be 
helpful in tlie development of the complete personality. 

Thus, in Froebel we see an attempt to reconcile the two 
divergent doctrines of education which thinkers before 
hiTn had held. He realized the value of natural growth and 
development, and did not want this warped or interfered 
with. But, he also realized that society plays a great part 
in making the person a civilized being. Thus, society 



224 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHU-OSOFHEBS 

should not be ignored, nor should the child be educated in 
complete disregard of the values of society. 

Consequently, social participation, work in groups, was a 
definite part of the kindergarten as conceived and founded 
by Fit>ebeL At the beginning of the kindergarten day the 
children gathered in a circle, each child holding the hands 
of those on either side of him. This circle was supposed to 
symbolize the unity of the group* Then the circle was 
broken up, and children played or worked either alone or 
in small groups. At the dose of the day the circle was 
again formed to emphasize that even though the child was 
an individual and should develop as such, he was also a 
member of the whole group. 

This problem of the individual and the group is still the 
major problem of present-day educational thinking. Public 
schools have been set up by society and are supported by 
means of taxes. Thus, society has said, in effect, that it 
recognizes the necessity of education for its preservation. 
Further, society has designated what shall be taught in 
these schools. Teachers are certified by society, and must 
meet certain standards set by society. 

AH of these factors indicate that society has a major 
interest in education. Therefore, there are many who argue 
today that the fundamental purpose of education is to 
train and mould individuals into service to the state. The 
whole totalitarian educational system in the twentieth- 
century dictatorships is of this nature. Education is con- 
trolled completely by the state and no one is permitted to 
do or teach anything except that which will contribute to 
the building of citizens who will devotedly serve the state 
and be obedient to the will of the ruler. 

But educators in the democratic countries see the danger 
of destroying the individuality of children. They feel that 
in so far as the individual is permitted to grow according 
to his nature and to deviate from the group, he is able to 
make a contribution to the groups such as will further 
group progress. 

One of the leaders in the field of education in our de- 
mocracy is JOHN DEWEY. His theories are in agreement 



MAN AND EDUCATION 

with those of men who believe that the center of education 
should be the individual child, Dewey recognizes, how- 
ever, that neither the individual nor the group should be 
given exclusive emphasis. The individual becomes truly 
developed as a member of society* Further, society has the 
right to demand of the individual that he prepare himself 
to serve the best interests of the group. But, Dewey holds 
that the best interests of the group will be served as the 
individual develops his own particular talents, as he de- 
velops his individual nature. Education is concerned with 
the individual in society and not with the individual iso- 
lated from society. 

This point of view has led to the development erf what 
is generally known today as the "child centered" school. 
In some instances this school has gone to the extreme of 
the philosophy upon which it is founded and has em- 
phasized the child's interests to the exclusion of all others. 
Many so-called "progressive* schools are of this type. But, 
the saner representatives of this movement, under the 
leadership of Dewey, have attempted to find an adequate 
adjustment and reconciliation between the two extremes of 
emphasis on the individual and on society. The result is a 
school in which individual interests, talents, and purposes 
are considered as means for contributing to the good of 
the whole. 



Chapter IX 
MIND AND MATTER 

ANAXAGORAS PLATO ABISTOTLE PHILO 

ANSELM ROGER BACON PARACELSUS 
FRANCES BACON HOBBES DESCARTES SPINOZA 

LOCKE BERKELEY KANT 
BRADLEY BOYCE JAMES DEWEY 



Is the universe actually fust a great mind, or Is it really 
matter throughout? Is matter mind or is mind matter? 
If His mfad and matter, what is the relation between 
the two? How can mind influence matter or matter i n- 
fluence mind? Have philosophers found a solution to 
the problem of the relationship between mind and 
matter? 



Anyone who opens his eyes to observe will discover a 
world of objects which con be kicked about, moved from 
place to place, broken into bits, shaped and moulded in 
many ways, but which do not "seem to care." A piece of 
day can be shaped into a thousand and one forms. A rock 
can be rolled about, broken into pieces, or ground into the 
finest powder. 

This individual who has noted these facts knows also 
that certain other objects seem "to care* what happens to 
them. Indeed he finds evidence that they make plans for 
their future and endeavor to carry them out. A man, for 
example, seems to plan his actions, to resist forces which 
would turn him from his plan, and is able to shape his 



MIND AJND MATTER 227 

environment to fit his plan. He moves into a barren land, 
draws plans for a giant irrigation system, builds the sys- 
tem, and eventually has changed an arid region to a mod- 
em Eden of flowers, trees, and green grass. 

The difference between the rode and man is, according 
to many philosophers, to be found in the fact that in man 
there is a mind which is absent in the rock. This mind, 
they argue, controls that part of the individual which is 
not mind. The not-mind is called matter. 

The earliest people of whom we know anything recog- 
nized this difference among objects in the environment 
Indeed, they recognized the difference within themselves. 
They experienced their bodies as composed of matter, but 
they were vaguely conscious that this mass of matter was 
animated by something which was distinct from matter, 
and different. As far back as we can penetrate into the be- 
ginnings of man's thinking, we find that he recognized a 
difference between mind and matter and that he placed 
mind in a more exalted realm than matter. 

The earliest beliefs regarding mind and matter were 
tied up with beliefs about the soul and the body. In the 
days of the childhood of humanity fofa thing which made 
man different from other things, this soul, was not clearly 
defined or understood. Indeed in many quarters early man 
believed that all the universe had a souL The rock, the tree, 
the river, all had souls as well as bodies. Later, as man 
developed, the idea of mind as a peculiar human posses- 
sion and distinct from matter became dearer. 

The Greeks exhibit all stages of this development, from 
the most primitive to a dear distinction between mind 
and matter. The first records whidi we have of the Greeks 
reveal them as nature-worshipers believing that everything 
in nature was possessed of a souL Gradually they de- 
veloped a mythology or group of stories about the activities 
of nature which they looked upon as alive. Then, as the 
Greeks came to distinguish between the animate and the 
inanimate, they no longer looked upon the rocks and trees 
as having souls, but they felt that gods presided over them. 
This was the period of the great theogonies or genealogies 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

of the gods who ruled over the various things in nature. 
Then, as the Greek mind matured, these inventions of 
fancy and of the childhood of the race gave place to more 
careful studies of nature and of man. The gods were put 
in a realm of celestial glory and more or less peace; nature 
was held to be alive but not possessed of a soul; man was 
believed to be a unique combination of soul and body. 
The Greek was studying his world and himself and was 
coming nearer and nearer to the belief that there must be 
a dear distinction between two phases of the universe, be- 
tween matter on the one hand and mind on the other, 
But, the fmaT realization of this distinction was a long and 
difficult process. 

Mind and Matter 3 Contrasted by the 
Early Greek Thinkers 

The first Greek philosophers were interested, as we have 
already seen, in the problem of the nature of the universe. 
They saw this universe as composed of one or more original 
and simple substances. But, to account for the fact that 
the basic substances became a universe, they introduced a 
force which in some way or other moved substance. ANAX- 
TMANPEB, for example, held that the basic substance of the 
universe was "the infinite," an eternal and imperishable 
substance. But he endowed this substance with eternal mo- 
tion in order to explain how the universe as he saw it and 
as his fellows saw it came into being. Here is an early dis- 
tinction between mass or substance and a force which 
moves it and shapes it into objects and things. 

This distinction runs through early Greek philosophy. 
Each thinker suggests some basic principle or substance of 
which the universe is composed, and accounts for its com- 
ing into being by adding another factor which is distinct 
from the basic substance and which makes it take the 
many forms which we see about us in the world. 

HEBAGLTTUS attempted to make the original substance 
and the cause of the forms which it takes one and the 
same, when he held that the first principle of the universe 
was fire as a symbol of change. He saw ceaseless activity 



MIND AND MATTEH 

everywhere and reasoned that change or activity was all 
that there was in the universe. Nevertheless, he felt that in 
addition to the fact of change there was some entity which 
changed, something different from the principle of change. 

When Heraclitus came to speak of man, he revealed 
this fact clearly. Here he made a distinction between man's 
body and his soul. The body was material and the soul 
was akin to divine reason. Thus, even in Heraclitus we find 
a distinction between ttat which moves and that which is 
moved. 

In PAEMENIDES we find a suggestion that thought or 
mind is in some way the creator or cause of that which is 
not mind. This is tie principle which much later devel- 
oped into the great idealistic movement Parmenides ar- 
gued that being and thought are one and the same, for 
what cannot be thought cannot be and what cannot be 
cannot be thought Thought, or mind, and being, or sub- 
stance, are identical to him. All reality, he held, is en- 
dowed with mind, and mind is, in some way not quite 
dear to him, the cause of everything. Mind causes matter 
to be, creates matter. Although Pannenides does not see 
all the implications of this position, and although he does 
not hold to this point of view consistently, we find in his 
writings a foreshadowing of one of the major positions 
regarding mind and matter, the position that actually mind 
is all that exists and that which we call matter is a creation 
of mind for its own purposes. 

By the time of ANAXAGOBAS, during the fifth century 
B.C., we have a clear statement of the theory that all 
movement is caused by mind or "nous* which is distinct 
from the substance that moves. This mind is, for Anaxag- 
oras, a free source of all movement Further, it knows all 
things in the past, in the present, and in the future, and is 
the arranger and cause of all things. 

Here Anaxagoras expressed fairly clearly what many 
philosophers before htm had been striving to express, a 
vague dualism between matter and something else which 
causes matter to move and become. But, for him, mind is 
not an individual thing to be found in each object. Rather, 



23 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

it is a world mind which is free from tlie individual objects 
of the universe but which serves as the moving principle 
in them. This world mind rules all things and does not get 
itself mixed up or mingled with things. It started the 
world, and is, in some way, in the world and the imme- 
diate cause of the world, 

Anaxagoras was anxious, as were most of the thinkers 
of his day, to explain the universe in purely mechanical 
terms. But he found instances in which this explanation 
did not seem to be adequate. Then he turned to the theory 
of the world mind As Aristotle points out in commenting 
on this point: ^Anaxagoras uses mind as a device by which 
to construct the universe, and when he is at a loss for an 
explanation of why anything necessarily is, then he drags it 
in; but in other cases he assigns any other cause rather 
than mind, for what comes into being,* In other words, 
Anaxagoras was struggling to get away from the idea that 
matter is not a self-contained principle, but he was still 
held by the beliefs of the past. 

The Sophists were not concerned with explanations of 
the nature of the universe. Indeed, most of them felt that 
all attempts to discover the origin of the universe or to 
locate the first substance or substances of which all else 
was created was nothing short of foolishness. They cen- 
tered their attention upon man and especially upon the 
mind of man. .They believed that this mind was the pivot 
about which all else revolved. All truth was, for them, 
measured by the mind of the individual man, so that what 
each man's mind told him was true was in fact true. Thus, 
the Sophists accepted the dualism between mind and mat- 
ter and held that mind was the determiner of all things. 

Plat o, Aristotle, and the Later Greek Philosophers 

The mind, which he also referred to as the soul, was for 
PLATO the seat of all knowledge. Ideas had been implanted 
in the mind before it became imbedded in the body. Birth 
clouded the mind, so that the individual forgot all that he 
knew. But, through a process of questioning it was pos- 
sible, Plato believed, to cause the mind to remember what 



MIND AND MATTER 231 

it had known before birth. All knowledge, Be held, was 
located in the mind, knowledge gained from experiences 
before birth. When this knowledge was recalled or remem- 
bered, the individual knew. 

Plato held firmly to the idea that the universe is com- 
posed of two principles; mind and matter. Mind is wholly 
distinct from matter. Matter is, for him, a dull weight that 
mind must carry because mind has become entangled with 
matter. Matter is the raw material upon which mind works. 
It has no oim or reality except as mind works on it and 
forms it into being. Mind is the only true reality, the thing 
of most worth, the principle of law and order in the 
universe. 

This matter, dead and thus a slave, is impressed by 
mind with the ideas which mind has experienced in the 
ideal world, ideas which are real and true. It takes the 
shape of these ideas, and holds this shape for some time. 
The tree which you and I see is not a real tree to Plato. It 
has come about because mind has taken some matter and 
impressed upon it the idea of tree. The true tree, the real 
tree exists only in the realm of ideas, and has been seen by 
mind before birth. . 

Plato resorts to a myth to explain how mind, pure and 
untarnished, originally got mixed up with matter. He says 
that it was existing on a star in its pure form but that it 
became possessed of a desire for the world of sense. There- 
fore it became imprisoned in a body. Here it seeks to free 
itself from the body and return to the star. This is, of 
course, not a satisfactory explanation; it is evidence of the 
fact that at this point Plato was not sure of himself. He 
was sensing what became later a most difficult problem: 
that of explaining the relationship between pure matter and 
pure mini How could these very opposite things ever 
come into any relationship with each other? This problem 
has haunted philosophers even to the present. Plato could 
not solve it; and it remains unsolved. 

ARISTOTLE could not solve it. But he sensed that the 
solution lay along the line of an intimate relationship be- 
tween the two. Mind, for him, was in matter as its forma- 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

tive principle, as its form. He held that there could be no 
matter without mind and no mind without matter. Even 
the lowest forms of matter known have form and therefore 
have mind. As we progress up the scale to man we find a 
clearer mind. But mind is everywhere. 

Mind, then, for Aristotle, is not outside of matter, as 
Plato had held, but is within matter as the cause of all 
that is. Matter has existence and offers resistance to mind 
which attempts to form it into shapes. At the same time, 
matter is the ground of beings and therefore must seek in 
some way to be shaped. Mind, then, has both an antagonist 
and a willing helper in matter. 

The Epicureans, in their attempt to explain the rela- 
tionship between the mind and the body, turned to the 
writings of Democritus. This ancient philosopher had ar- 
gued that aH sense perception results from "idols'* or im- 
ages which objects throw off and which hit the sense 
organs. For example, when I see a chair my eyes are be- 
ing bombarded by little idols of the chair which it is con- 
stantly throwing off. These little images travel through 
space to the eye, and I see a chair. 

In the same way, the Epicureans argued, when I want 
to ran, an image of running presents itself to the mind* 
Then the mind hits the soul with the image. Since the 
soul is spread aH over the body, it hits the body witih this 
image, and the body runs. This appears very crude and 
unbelievable today, but it was an earnest attempt to ex- 
plain how mind, which, was so different from matter, could 
influence matter so that when the mind has an idea the 
body acts in accord with it 

The Stoics held that mind is material just as is matter, 
but of a much finer texture. It is a spark of the divine fire. 
The mind is, for them, the soul become rational or having 
acquired the power of conceptual thought. Thus, mind is 
distinct from matter only in degree, not in kind. 

The Skeptics, such as PYRBHO, held that it was impos- 
sible to prove that matter existed, since all that we have 
is our ideas or thoughts. To demonstrate that something 
exists which corresponds to our thoughts is impossible. 



MIND AND MATTEH 233 

Thus, all that we have is ideas in the mind. We must act 
upon these, hoping that we will get what we expect, but 
with no assurance. Mind exists, but there is no proof that 
matter exists. 

The Positions of Philo and St. Augustine 
As Greek thought came into contact with the Jewish 
religious thought of men like PHILO the attempt was made 
to find a basis for reconciling the ideas of both traditions of 
thought. Philo, being fundamentally interested in religion, 
thought of God as the world mind which shapes matter. 
Thus, the universe for him is composed of mind and mat- 
ter. Likewise, man is a dualism of mind and matter. Pure 
thought, "nous," is the chief essence of man, and matter 
or the body is that upon which mind works. Thus mind 
in man controls his body or matter, just as the world mind, 
God, controls matter in the world. Pure intelligence is 
added to the soul from God, thus tying man on to the di- 
vine in the universe. 

Christianity brought to the front the idea that matter is 
the source of all evil, a thing to be shunned. Matter holds 
the soul down and therefore must be denied by the soul 
if it is to attain salvation. Thus, throughout most of early 
Christian thinking we find a definite despising of matter. 
Although matter had been thought of by early philoso- 
phers as something less than mind, dead, or the material 
upon which mind worked, there was never that complete 
degradation of matter which characterized Christianity. 
Further, there was not the earnest desire to escape from 
matter, a desire born of fear of matter. Early C^hristianity 
taught man that matter was the source of all evil and that 
man's salvation lay in his turning away from matter to 
pure spirit or God. 

AUGUSTINE recognized the difference between mind and 
matter in man, but held that truth is not something which 
the human mind creates. Rather, truth is, for him, some- 
thing that exists independently of mind, and has its source 
in God. Mind may discover truth, just as the Platonic 



234 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

mind saw ideas in the ideal world. For Augustine, the mind 
of God is the abode of ideas and of truth. 

According to the Medieval Christian Thinkers 

Christianity emphasized another principle which had a 
telling effect upon man. Not only did it disparage matter 
by making it the source of evil, but it disparaged the hu- 
man mind. This was done to elevate God to the place in 
the universe which Christian thinkers believed He should 
have. 

The human mind, Christian philosophers taught, is a 
poor and inefficient instrument. It is full of mistakes and 
of error. Of course, man can use his mind to reason, but 
his conclusions must conform to the divine authority. No 
one could be permitted to reach a conclusion through use 
of his mind which in any way questioned the edicts of 
authority. The church and its doctrines were believed to 
be the ultimate in truth. Augustine had held that truth 
was independent of the human mind. Therefore, the func- 
tion of the mind was not to create truth but to discover it 
When the Church ruled that a certain doctrine was true, 
the human mind had to accept it without question. AN- 
SELM held to this position finnly. He argued that the hu- 
man .mind may try to understand the doctrines of the 
Church, but if it is unable to reach understanding, it must 
accept them just the same. This was the early position of 
Christian thinkers: the more contradictory to reason a thing 
is the more faith it takes to believe. But the human mind 
must never question. Belief must precede reason. 

When ABELAKD took the position that reason should pre- 
cede faith, he was going against a long and honored tra- 
dition. But Abelaxd never for a moment doubted that rea- 
son would prove the Christian doctrines to be true. He was 
willing to give the human mind freedom to question doc- 
trines, but he was certain that true reasoning would bring 
the mind to accept the doctrines as true and beyond ques- 
tion. Nevertheless, when once the human mind was per- 
mitted to question Christian doctrine the stability of this 
doctrine was in danger. Man was no longer beaten down 



MIND AND MATTER 23$ 

by authority and began to venture out to challenge doc- 
trine. The human mind, which had been held within a 
body of accepted doctrines for many centuries, began after 
Abelard to feel its way toward independence* 

The result was nothing short o revolutionary. Once the 
restraint was eased, man began to think about many things 
and to question much that he had not dared to question 
previously. He began to exercise his mind and to wrestle 
with numerous problems which he had shunned or not 
even seen previously. A new and exciting world dawned. 

THOMAS AQUINAS, though developing a position which 
was fundamentally religious, sought to champion the hu- 
man mind by endeavoring to show that the universe as a 
revelation of God is rational Recognizing the power of the 
mind, he sought to show that Christianity, as interpreted 
by the church, was logically consistent In doing this, he 
fell within that tradition which was becoming so important, 
a tradition in which the human mind was fast becoming 
the court of final appeal No longer was it possible for any 
institution, even the church, to disregard human reason or 
to insult it by proposing doctrines which were not con- 
sistent with the best that the mind knew. 

It was dear to Aquinas that man was both, mind and 
matter and that the two were intimately connected. How- 
ever, he did not believe that mind was so tied to the body 
that it could not function in more or less complete freedom 
from he ills of matter. Indeed, even though matter was 
the seat of evfl, mind was able to criticize matter and escape 
from it and its temptations. 

Roger Bacon and Paracelsus 

With the rise of natural science, the human mind began 
to assume a more important place in the scheme of things* 
ROGER BACON, a peculiar mixture of medieval monk and 
modern scientific scholar, stood midway between the old 
religious point of view and the more modern position of 
trust in the mind* He set about to use the mind to under- 
stand, and, in a small degree, to control matter. And he was 
startled to find that he could not only know, but could 



236 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PEQDLOSOPIIERS 

control matter. In him, then, we see the symbol of hu- 
manity feeling its wings, of the mind attacking the world 
of matter and realizing success which acted as a spur to 
further attacks and a growing confidence in the power of 
the mind. 

It was inevitable that free thought should assume a more 
and more prominent place in the new world, which was 
coming into being. As man thought and found thinking 
good, he would think more, and gradually become impa- 
tient with any authority which denied him the right to 
thinL Success bred courage, and courage resulted in more 
use of the mind and more success. There was no stopping 
this process once it was begun. 

Of course, it was inevitable that the first blush of success 
should lead to extravagances, to an over-enthusiasm re- 
garding the powers of the mind. In a man like PARACEL- 
SUS, for example, we see evidences of this over-enthusiasm. 
He visioned short cuts to mental mastery of the universe, 
and suggested many strange things which today appear 
little other than pure superstitions. Alchemy and magic ap- 
peared to him, to be ways by which mind might master 
matter. 

But these vagaries were soon to be corrected by men 
who saw further and saw clearer. The great scientists, 
among whom were GALILEO, KEPLER, NEWTON, and 
others, realized that the mastery of the understanding of 
matter by mind was a long and arduous task, requiring 
careful study and a growing keenness of understanding. 
They set man on this hard road with definiteness, and 
proved by their successes that this was the only road to 
success. 

Francis Bacon and Hobbes 

Then came FRANCIS BACON (not to be confused with 
Roger Bacon), a man who could take the modern spirit of 
confidence in the power of the human mind and the 
equally modern science and weave them together so as to 
suggest a method by which mind could master the uni- 



AND MATTER 237 

verse. He showed tow this new-found strength could be 
used and how it could lead to success. 

Francis Bacon's method was fairly simple as we look at 
it today. He would first dear the mind of all "idols" or false 
ways of thinking. lien, as a free instrument, the mind 
could attack the world by careful observation, the collec- 
tion of data, and the interpretation of these data. This was 
the method of "induction,* the moving from numerous bits 
of evidence to a general principle which will explain the 
data collected. Here was a method which mind could em- 
ploy, and which, Bacon believed, would lead inevitably to 
success. Thus, he set the pattern for thinking, and chal- 
lenged men to think clearly and accurately. 

But inevitably the question as to the rektionship be- 
tween mind and matter would arise. Though some earKer 
philosophers had attacked the problem, they were not in 
any position to do more than sketch in its bold outline. 
Then, during those early days of the Renaissance, when 
man was enchanted by the new-felt power which he was 
discovering, the question faded into the background. Man 
was more interested in using his mind than in asking ques- 
tions about it Nevertheless, sooner or later it was certain 
that the question would arise again and demand solution. 

With THOMAS HOBBES we have an early modern at- 
tempt to explain the relationship between mind and matter. 
Being a materialist and believing that everything could be 
explained in material terms, Hobbes taught that mind is 
motion in the brain. In other places he refers to mind as an 
internal substance, a subtle body, in the head. When the 
mind has an idea, there is nothing more than motion of a 
material substance in the brain. Here Hobbes seems to 
solve the problem of the relationship between mind and 
matter by holding that mind is matter and that there is no 
difference. Mind is simply a more subtle matter than that 
of body. This was the ynnfcmt explanation. 

But, though a materialist, Hobbes does not seem content 
with this explanation. In other passages we find him speak- 
ing of mental processes as appearances of motion, as the ef- 
fects of motion rather than as motion itself. Consciousness 



238 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

comes after motion as its effect This theory is known in 
modern philosophy as *epiphenomenalism. w 

Thus, though Hobbes attempts to account for mind in 
terms of matter, he is not quite satisfied with the results, 
and seems at times to drift in the direction of a dualism one 
side of which is motion and the other side the effect of 
motion, 

Descartes and Spinoza 

The same problem challenged DESCARTES. He did not 
try to dodge the issue, but stated clearly that the universe, 
for him, consisted of two substances, mind and body. And 
these two substances were fundamentally different If, then, 
mind is wholly different from body or matter, how is it 
that mind can have an effect upon matter or move the 
body? How is it that when one wishes to walk, he walks? 

TTie solution which Be offers is vague and full of con- 
fusion. Determined to stick to his dualism, a complete and 
absolute dualism, he has difficulty in explaining interac- 
tion. Mind, he tells us, is troubled by matter, by the proc- 
esses which go on in the body. At another place he offers 
an interesting but not wholly satisfying explanation of in- 
teraction. He suggests that the body and the mind make 
contact through the pineal gland, a small gland in the 
brain* The body, he says, moves the pineal gland or the 
mind moves it In either case this movement is transmitted 
to the other which is itself moved: I wish to walk; I trans- 
mit motion to the pineal gland which transmits it to the 
body; and I walk. 

The unsatisfactoriness o this theory is proof of the fact 
that Descartes, having once taken his stand as to the dif- 
ferences between mind and matter, could not find any ex- 
planation of the experienced fact of interaction. It seems 
that he must either deny interaction and leave the question 
unsolved, or take the position that mind and matter are 
enough alike to influence each other. 

Descartes* successors rejected the idea of interaction and 
sought to explain the relationship between mind and mat- 
ter by some other principle, ARNOLD GUEUNCX taught that 



MINB AND MATTEB 239 

God has so arranged the universe from the beginning that 
when the mind has an idea, matter moves as though it 
were affected, but actually there is no interaction. God 
created the world and in this creation he so determined 
everything that when my mind has an idea of walking my 
body walks. Guelincx writes that "God in his infinite wis- 
dom has instituted laws of motion, so that a movement 
which is entirely independent of my will and power coin- 
cides with my free volition," 

NICOLAS MAEKBRANCHS held that we do not experience 
a world of matter and are not affected by that world. 
Rather, God is like mind, and influences our minds so that 
we think we experience a material world. Indeed, he tells 
us, "If God had destroyed the created world, and would 
continue to affect me as he now affects me, I should con- 
tinue to see what I now see; and I should believe that this 
(created) world exists, since it is not this world that acts on 
my mind" but God himself. 

Another point of view, held by many Cartesians, was 
that whenever something happens in matter, God affects 
us so that we think we are being affected by the happening 
in matter. This is known as the theory of "occasionalism": 
the happening in the material world is the occasion for 
God's action upon us. 

These theories, as it should be clear, are not at all satis- 
factory. They make of God a sort of showman putting on 
a performance for us, fooling us by pilling the proper 
strings at the proper time. One is tempted to ask the ques- 
tion, if God created the world, why did he create such a 
situation? Would it not have been easier to have created a 
world in which mind and matter interacted? 

But philosophers were not contented, and they struggled 
to reach a more acceptable theory of the relationship be- 
tween mind and matter. SPINOZA taught that mind and 
matter were two attributes of one and the same substance, 
God. These two attributes were, for him, absolutely inde- 
pendent of each other and neither could influence the 
other. But, since they are attributes of God, we have 
thought and action moving along in parallel lines, both 



240 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

being the thought and action of God. This is the theory of 
*psychophysical parallelism.** My mind, Spinoza would 
argue, is a mode of the thinking attribute of God, and my 
body is a mode of the extended attribute of God. My 
thought is paralleled by action in the body so that it ap- 
pears that my mind influences my body. Actually there is 
BO direct influence. 

Locke, 'Berkeley 9 and Hume 

JOHN LOCKE abandoned the attempt to malce two unlike 
tilings influence each other. He begins his thinking with the 
tihesis that the mind is a sort of blank tablet upon which 
the world of matter writes by means of sensations. This 
mind does not have innate or inborn ideas, but it does have 
the power to arrange impressions in such a way as to pro- 
duce a consistent system of thoughts. Mind and body, for 
Lodfae, exist as real things, but they interact Bodies act 
upon the mind and produce sensations. Locke spends a 
great deal of time developing this point of view, but, when 
he comes up against the question as to how these two un- 
like substances interact, he is confused, and even though 
he does not want to, he lapses into occasionalism. 

Accepting the dualism of mind and body as his starting 
point, GEORGE BERKELEY draws the conclusion that the 
material cannot exist and that the only thing that we can 
prove as existing is mind. Matter, belief in which leads to 
atheism and materialism, as he argued, cannot exist. To 
exist means to be perceived, therefore bodies have no ex- 
istence without mind. The mind creates the material world, 
and this world has existence only in mind. This is the ideal- 
istic position in modern philosophy. 

DAVID HXJME went a step further and showed that, on 
the basis of Locke's dualism, we cannot prove even the 
existence of mind. All that we can prove is that ideas, im- 
pressions, come one after tte other. Whence they come 
cannot be proven. There is, for Hume, no material world 
and no mind; just a succession of impressions. 

Philosophy could not stand this very logical position. 
Since it was logical, thinkers began to ask if the premises 



MIND ANJ> SCATTER 

upon which It was based, those of a dualism between mind 
and matter, might not be false. 

The Views of Leibnitz 

LEIBNITZ attacked the problem by holding that body, or 
matter, is not something dead and static, but is composed 
of many monads or centers of force. These monads differ 
in clearness of their perceptions, and mind consists of these 
perceptions. Every monad or center of force has the power 
of perception. It perceives or represents and expresses in 
itself the entire universe. The higher the monad, the clearer 
are these perceptions. 

For Leibnitz the human organism contains a central 
monad or "queen monad" which has before it the picture 
of the entire body. God, in creating the world, so arranged 
things that the monads composing the body and the 
"queen monad" are m perfect hannony. "Souls act/* he 
writes, "according to the laws of final causes, by means of 
desire, ends, and means. Bodies act according to the laws of 
efficient causes or motions. And the two realms are in har- 
mony with one another." 

It is evident that here Leibnitz is attempting to erase to 
some extent the complete difference between mind and 
matter by holding that both are centers of force and that 
the "queen monad" is simply a clearer and more perfect 
monad than those composing matter or the body. Al- 
though no monad, whether it be "queen" or less clear 
monad, can influence another monad, there is a certain re- 
lationship among monads. The mind or soul monad holds 
its place because it is a better monad, not because it is 
something different from other monads. 

Kant and Later German Philosophers 

With KANT there emerged a fairly clear-cut theory of 
the -mind as the only source of knowledge. While Kant 
admitted the existence of a world other than the mind, a 
world from which the mind received impressions, he held 
that the mind can know nothing of this world, this *thing- 
in-itself ? The mind receives impressions according to its 



242 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

nature or its categories and shapes them into patterns 
which conform not to the world outside mind, but to the 
nature of mind. 

We know, then, only what our mind shapes and moulds. 
We can, because of the necessities of the moral nature, be- 
lieve in the existence of the "thing-in-itself,** but mind can 
never prove it, nor can mind prove what it would be 
without mind. Indeed, we are shut up in our minds, and 
must interpret everything in terms of our minds. Space and 
time, for example, are not realities existing by themselves, 
but are ways our minds have of receiving and shaping sen- 
sations. Take away the thinking subject," Kant argues, 
"and the entire corporeal world will vanish, for it is noth- 
ing but the appearance in the sensibility of our subject* 

Kant* s position gave rise to the great German Idealistic 
movement of the eighteenth century. Thinkers who fol- 
lowed him felt that the only solution of the problem of 
mind and matter lay in eliminating matter. This seemed 
the most logical approach. Mind seemed evident, but mat- 
ter had to be interpreted as something other thgn and out- 
side of mind, different from mind. But this gave rise to the 
problem of how these two so different things could interact. 
This problem and aH its difficulties could be eliminated by 
doing away with matter. Such a solution, as we have seen, 
was not new, but it was greatly strengthened by the work 
which Kant had done. He had pointed the way and pro- 
duced strong evidence that this way was right and .true. 

JOHANN GOTTLIEB FicsTE took his cue from Kant and 
argued that the -mind, or ego, was everything, and that 
there was nothing outside of it He held that Kant's "thing- 
in-itself* could not possibly exist outside of the mind. The 
material world is, for him, a creation of the mind and serves 
as a limiting principle for the mind.' The material world is 
a projection into space of objects which exist only in the 
mind. 

However, the mind which creates this world is not the 
mind of the individual, according to Fichte, but is a uni- 
versal mind, an absolute ego. This universal mind is before 
and above all individual minds and is the creator of the 



MIND AND MASTER 243 

material world which has existence only in the universal 
mind. The material world "is not a world of dead things, 
arranged in a spatial-temporal-causal order; the latter is 
the re velation in human consciousness of the absolute prin- 
ciple, and could not exist if it were not for the universal 
ego.* Fichte seeks to solve the problem of mind and matter 
by making matter a creation of Tnfnci and denying it any 
existence other than that supplied it by mind* 

FRIEDBICH WELHELM SCHEDULING leaned heavily on 
Fichte in developing his theory of mind. For him, the ab- 
solute mind has limited itself in creating the material world* 
But, this material world is alive; it is mind at a lower level, 
a less clear level Actually there is only a difference of de- 
gree between the material world and mind. They are both 
mind of a certain sort 

Although lie approaches this question somewhat dif- 
ferently, HEGEL follows in frhig same idealistic tradition. 
For him, mind passes through three stages of evolution: 
subjective mind, objective mind, and absolute mind The 
subjective mind is dependent upon nature as soul, is op- 
posed to nature as consciousness, and is reconciled with 
nature as spirit At its highest, mind is creative of the 
world which it knows. 

Mind, for Hegel, is creative of the material world, there- 
fore in both that world and in mind we discover the same 
dialectical principles. Throughout the universe Hegel finds 
mind creating and realizing itself in objects and institutions. 

This idealistic tradition, developing out of Kanf s think- 
ing, held sway in Germany for a century. However, it was 
not satisfying to all philosophers. Many believed that the 
material world was too real to be explained merely as a 
creation of mind, whether it be individual mind or absolute 
mind. HEBBART is representative of this position. He held 
that *things~in-themselves* do exist and the world is not 
merely our idea. He based his thinking upon the premise 
that experience is the only source of knowledge. 

Every sensation is a sensation of something outside of the 
mind. Thus, there must be a real world which influences 
the mind This world is composed, according to Herbart, 



244 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

of many simple principles or "reals. 3 * This world of reals is 
static and unchanging. The soul is a real which asserts it- 
self against other reals and thus produces sensations in it- 
self. These sensations, as they are organized, constitute the 
mind. Mental life is, for him, a most complicated fusion of 
ideas, a union and organization of sensations which be- 
come ideas or units of the mind. Mind, then, is material, of 
the same general nature as the material world, 

Bradley, Royce, and Bergson 

There are three principal answers to the question of the 
relationship between mind and the material universe. One 
answer is that of Idealism, which holds that mind is in 
some way the creator of that which appears as matter. The 
method by which mfod creates matter may be thought of 
differently by various idealists, but in every case it is mind 
which is the real thing, and matter is a creation of mind, 
dependent upon mind for its existence. The more recent 
Idealists, F. EL BBADIJSY, JOSIAH ROYCE, HENBJ BEBGSON, 
and others, develop this position in one way or another. 

Gonfie, James, T>ewey, Santayana 

Another approach is that of Realism. Here it is held that 
mind and the material world are actually both material. 
The realists hold that mind is another form of the material 
world, finer perhaps, but actually material. Recent repre- 
sentatives of Realism are the Positivist, AUGUSTS COMTE, 
and the Pragmatists, WTT.TJAM JAMES and JOHN DEWEY. 
Although these men differ in many respects, they agree 
that mind is a kind of behavior. We have, for example, acts 
which are of such a nature as to be held mind-less. Other 
acts have a different nature, and we can refer to them as 
minded or having the characteristic of mind. Thus, for 
these philosophers mind is not a thing but is rather a kind 
of behavior. 

With the modern emphasis upon natural science and a 
moving away on the part of many philosophers from the 
more spiritual interpretation of the universe, the idealistic 
position has been in an eclipse. The materialistic point of 



MIND AND MATTER 5&4S 

view has seemed most logical In a world of natural science. 
BERTRAND RUSSEUL, has been more at home in this modern 
world than GEORGE SANTAYAKA. John Dewey has expressed 
the thoughts of the man in the machine shop and on the 
street, the man of "common sense," more completely than 
did Fichte or Hegel. 

But, with the coming of the present-day world, a world 
in which men are questioning the materialistic premises 
seriously, there are indications that some new form of 
Idealism is just over the horizon. Values, spiritual experi- 
ences, ideals and aspirations do not seem to be accounted 
for completely by materialism. There is a growing feeling 
among present-day thinkers that the next great step in phi- 
losophy will be a new Idealism. 



Chapter X 
IDEAS AND THINKING 

HERACLITUS SOCRATES PLATO ABISTOTLE 

GALILEO DESCARTES SPINOZA 

LOCKE KANT HEGEL COMTE 

MILL JAMES DEWEY 



Whence come our ideas? Are they lorn with us and 
do they become conscious in time, or do we get them 
from sense experiences? Or does some god reveal them 
to us? What are the laws of thinking? How do the 
thinkers of each age go about thinking? 



Everyone thinks. We all have "ideas* or thoughts, we 
see the world about us, and remember what we see. We 
make inferences from the facts which we experience, draw 
conclusions, and make these the bases of our actions. Man, 
we hold, is a thfaVfag being. 

Whether or not animals think has been a question of 
interest for generations. Your dog sees, hears, and feels. He 
receives impressions from his environment Further, he ap- 
pears to draw conclusions from these impressions and to 
act upon them. He finds that an individual is friendly, and 
he acts accordingly. He finds that another individual is not 
friendly, and acts upon this fact Does your dog think? 
Does he have ideas? 

The earliest philosophers struggled with the problems 
which grouped themselves around the question of ideas 
and thinking. How is it that ideas are formed? Where do 



IDEAS AND 1HINXING 247 

we get our ideas, and of what nature are they? How do we 
reach conclusions upon which we act? How do we come 
to know that one act will bring happiness and another mis- 
ery? All these, and many other problems, have appeared 
upon the pages of philosophic writings from the very be- 
ginning of human thought, and they still fascinate phi- 
losophers. 

When early man gave thought to these problems, he 
reached the only conclusion possible in his culture. He be- 
lieved that his ideas came to hfm from the world of spirits 
which surrounded him at all times. Cods put good ideas in 
his mind, and demons put evil ideas there. He felt that his 
thoughts came from outside himself, from the forces and 
powers which governed and controlled every phase of his 
life. 

In the history of philosophy, the explanation of ideas and 
thinking has tended steadily away from the supernatural 
Man has struggled to explain tTifalring in natural terms jmd 
as a result of natural processes and subject to natural laws. 

What Thinking Meant to the Early Greek Philosophers 

The early Greek philosophers were interested primarily 
in the nature of substance and gave little attention to man 
and his thought processes. They centered their attention 
upon nature, the world in which man lived, and attempted 
to explain how it came to be and what was its essence. 
HERACLTTDS was one of the few who gave some attention 
to the problem of thinking. He felt that reason was a more 
certain source of knowledge than sense perception and 
that the rational life was the best life. Reason, for him, was 
akin to divine reason, a sort of spark of the divine in man, 
which was able to see truth in ways not given to man de- 
void of reason. Most men, he said, live not by reason but 
by passion, 

EMPEDOCLES believed that since y^n knew the elements 
of which the universe is created, he must be composed of 
these elements. Like is known bjr like, he argued. There- 
fore, if man knows the universe, he must be like the uni- 
verse. Man knows water because particles of water pass 



248 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

from water to the eye and are there met by particles of 
water in the eye. This contact of water with water enables 
man to know water. He applied this same line of reasoning 
to man's knowledge of other things in the universe. 

Sense experience, for DEMOCBJTUS, was obscure knowl- 
edge. We really know, he argued, when we transcend sense 
perception. When sense perception can cany us no further, 
genuine knowledge begins. Here we are in a realm that 
deak with finer things than the senses can show us, the 
realm of true knowledge. 

These early Greeks, though interested primarily in the 
problems of the nature of substance, recognized that man's 
ability to have ideas, to know the world about him, pre- 
sented an equally difficult problem. But their suggested 
solutions of this problem were in line with their materialis- 
tic bent. In some way, they felt, ideas and the material 
world must be similar, though perhaps finer. 

This interest of the early Greek thinkers in the nature 
of the universe seemed a great waste of time to the Soph- 
ists. They felt that the many theories suggested by differ- 
ent thinkers pointed to the fact that no real explanation 
was possible. Thus, they turned from such questions to con- 
cern themselves with man. And tibe conclusion of their 
study was that tibe knowing subject was the thing of most 
importance and therefore that which should be studied* 
Further, they concluded that knowledge depends wholly 
upon the individual knower. My ideas are true for me and 
youis for you, they would say. For them there could be no 
objective absolute truth which would be the same for all 
men. Rather, that which seems true to a man is true for 
him. "Man," PHOTAGOBAS held, "is the measure of all 
things," even truth. 

This criticism of knowledge, this making of all knowl- 
edge dependent upon the individual knower, was a chal- 
lenge to those who assumed without question man's ability 
to know truth. By denying the possibility of sure and uni- 
versal knowledge, the Sophists made ft necessary for phi- 
losophers to investigate thinking most carefully and 
thereby opened the door for a theory of knowledge. They 



IDEAS AND THINKING 249 

hastened the discovery of the correct laws of thought and 
the development of "logic/* which is the science of thought 

According to Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle 

SOCRATES took up the challenge of the Sophists and as- 
serted without hesitation that the problem of knowledge 
was the key to all other problems. He was interested par- 
ticularly in discovering a method for reaching true knowl- 
edge as distinct from mere opinion. The method which he 
developed consisted of first clearing away all false notions 
and then proceeding with careful observation and thinking 
in order to reach universal judgments. Amid the diversity 
of thought Socrates attempted to discover that which was 
common to all, a ground which could not be disputed. 

By constant questioning and careful examination of 
statements and opinions, Socrates proceeded to establish 
definitions which he later used as bases for further opinions 
and statements of fact Having established a principle, he 
used it to define other principles. 

It is customary to speak of logic as either inductive or 
deductive. Induction consists in starting with some parties 
lar fact and arriving at a general principle. Deduction starts 
with a general principle and shows its application to par- 
ticular facts. Deduction is the more characteristic method 
of the early thinkers; and induction is the method of mod- 
em science. Socrates used something of both methods. 

PLATO was among the first philosophers to offer a fairly 
complete theory of knowledge. He agreed with Socrates 
that sense perception could not give genuine knowledge. 
Man must pass beyond the senses to ideas which are not 
derived from experience and are not dependent upon ex- 
perience. The soul, he taught, comes into the world cany- 
ing within itself true ideas. These have been planted in it in 
an existence previous to birth. True knowledge is reached 
when these ideas are remembered and take the front of 
consciousness. This is "conceptual knowledge" as distin- 
guished from sense knowledge which is actually not knowl- 
edge. This reveals the essence of things rather than their 
mere accidental factors. 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

ABISTOTLE carried this line of reasoning further by hold- 
ing that although our world of experience is the real world, 
genuine knowledge consists of knowing the reasons or 
causes of things* To reach these basic causes man must 
follow certain laws of logic or true processes of thought. 
The pattern of true thought is, he argued, the "syllogism,* 
in which we move from a generally accepted principle to a 
particular. 

A famous example of the syllogism is; 

AH men are mortaL 
Socrates is a man. 
Therefore Socrates is mortal* 

All men are mortaL This is a general principle which is 
evidenced through numerous experiences. We may look 
about us and, after observing a number of men and seeing 
that all sooner or later die, reach the general conclusion 
that all men are mortal Since Socrates was a man, he can 
be classified under the general heading of *all men." What 
is true about afl men must be true about Socrates* If aH 
men are mortal, the particular man Socrates must also be 
mortal* 

Aristotle worked out the science of deductive logic so 
completely that.Iittle or nothing has been added to it even 
to the present. He laid down all the laws and gave ex- 
amples which men have been able to follow with success 
ever since. 

The Views of the Later Greek Philosophers 

EPICURXJS turned to the senses as the criterion of truth. 
We must, he argued, trust our senses. All knowledge comes 
through the senses, and error is a mistake in judgment. If 
we observe correctly, we arrive at truth. When we make 
false interpretations of our sensations, or refer them to the 
wrong objects, we make mistakes and do not have true 
knowledge. We learn, then, by using our senses, and we 
must be very careful that we use them correctly. 

We perceive copies of objects, and these are true copies 
since they come directly from the objects themselves. These 



IDEAS AND imNKXNG 251 

copies strike the sense organs and produce ideas in us. If 
we do not get our ideas mixed up, we have the truth about 
the real world. 

The Stoics agreed with the Epicureans in holding that 
all knowledge comes through sense perception. At birth, 
they maintained, the soul is an empty tablet which receives 
impressions from things. These impressions persist and form 
memory-images, and from these images ideas are formed. 
The mind organizes its impressions into general ideas. Thus, 
all knowledge which we have comes, they hold, from im- 
pressions and our organizing of these. If we have an im- 
mediate conviction that there is a real object correspond- 
ing to our idea, then that real object does exist 

It is evident that the Stoics disagreed completely witi 
Plato. Ideas are not in the soul at birth, as Pkto had ar- 
gued. They come to the soul from the outside and through 
the senses. The mind does not have ideas until the senses 
give it impressions which it can organize into ideas. Pkto 
was a "rationalist" in holding that the mind has ideas in- 
dependently of experience. The Stoics were ''empiricists'' 
in holding that ideas come from experience. 

Greek thought gave us these two great traditions in phi- 
losophy. The rationalists held that the ideas which man has 
are innate. Experience simply serves to stir them into con- 
sciousness. The empiricists held that the mind has no ideas 
of its own. It looks out upon the world through the win- 
dows of the senses. When these senses are stimulated by 
this outer world, they impress these experiences upon the 
mind, which in turn organizes them into ideas. The prog- 
ress of philosophy is more or less a battle between various 
forms of these two major positions as regards ideas. 

The Medieval Christian View 

One phase of the conflict between the Nominalists and 
the Realists among the medieval Christian philosophers 
was concerned with thinking. The Realists held that ideas 
are general concepts or universals which have an existence 
independently of *Mngg or experiences. Ideas are real in the 
sense that they are not created by the individual's experi- 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHTLOSOPIEEIlS 

ences. The Nominalists lield that Ideas are the results of 
experience and can have no existence except as they are 
supported by experience. We build general ideas, such as 
justice and goodness, out of experiences; and without ex- 
periences, individual and unique experiences, we could 
have no general ideas. 

With AUGUSTINE we find ourselves in a period one of the 
chief characteristics of which was a distinction between 
ordinary ideas received through experience and revealed 
knowledge received from God. Augustine held that man 
has natural knowledge of the world about him. He knows 
physical nature, and can act on this knowledge. For the 
ordinary needs of living this knowledge is sufficient. But 
there is also a higher knowledge which comes not from 
experiencing nature, nor is it of the same kind as natural 
knowledge. This is revealed knowledge, which comes 
through faith. 

In this way Augustine and the Christian scholars sought 
to protect the doctrines of the Church* Many of these doc- 
trines were not in accord with the logic of human think- 
ing. They seemed to contradict everything which man 
found in experience. But these thinkers held that they were 
true because of a knowledge different from and above 
natural knowledge. I know because God has revealed it to 
me, was the position taken by them. 

This interpretation enabled the Church to extend the 
borders of knowledge far beyond that of natural experi- 
ence. When man reached the limits of his ability to do 
logical thinking, to reason in line with the principles of 
Aristotle, he was able, by this method of divine knowledge, 
to go on to accept the doctrines of the Church. 

This position became fundamental to the Church's phi- 
losophy, and developed into the doctrine of the "two-f old 
truth,** One phase of truth is that which can be substanti- 
ated by logical reasoning. Another phase is that which is 
substantiated by faith and the authority of the Church. 
THOMAS AQUINAS made this basic to his general position. 
One phase of his thinking dealt with ideas received from 
sensations. He argued that genuine knowledge is concep- 



IDEAS ANB THINKING 

tual knowledge and that concepts have their origin in 
sations. But the mind is able to form universal notions 
from these sensations. External objects act on the souL 
This raw material of knowledge is received and worked 
into conceptual knowledge by the higher faculties of the 
soul. 

But there is also intuitive knowledge which is superior to 
knowledge gained through sensations, through reason, or 
through mere faith. This knowledge has its source in divine 
revelation and also gains its authority from the divine. We 
know about God, immortality, the divinity of Jesus, and 
other doctrines of the Church, not by reasoning, but by 
tibis higher type of knowledge. 

JOHN DUNS Scorus goes further ffiflp Aquinas in limiting 
the sphere of reason. He did not believe that any of the 
Church's doctrines could be demonstrated by reason, and 
held that they all depended upon revelation. Reason, he 
held, could not prove these doctrines, but it was in perfect 
harmony with them* If, however, reason reached conclu- 
sions different from the doctrines of the Church, reason 
had to bow to superior authority and admit that it was 
wrong. 

Thus, although Christian thinkers accepted the two-fold 
truth, it is evident that knowledge coining from divine reve- 
lation was thought to be superior to that coming from ex- 
perience. The natural result was that human reason was 
constantly being corrected by the Church. Ideas which men 
gained by hard thinking were found to be opposed to the 
authority of religion, and the Church was powerful enough 
to suppress such conclusions in the interest of what it held 
to be revealed knowledge. 

Galileo and the Beginning of the Scientific Attitude 

This condition could not, of course, continue indefinitely. 
As man began to gain confidence in himself end to chal- 
lenge the authority of the Church along other lines, it was 
inevitable that Le would challenge the authority of re- 
vealed knowledge. As tibis developed strength, the funda- 
mental bases of Scholastic thought began to crumble, and 
man stood more and more upon his own intellectual feet. 



254 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

He saw the power of sense experience and the equal power 
of reasoning from premises such as Aristotle had estab- 
lished The syllogism and sense experience gained in re- 
spect among men and the authority of the Church began 
to weaken. Man was demanding that all knowledge rest 
upon the ability of the human mind and not upon some 
revealed authority. 

GAIJLEO, as representative of this movement rejected 
authority and mystical speculation in matters of science, 
and held that all our ideas should rest upon observation or 
experimentation. But, he would add to experience, under- 
standing. He would build ideas out of observation, experi- 
ment, and thought. 

The scientists of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries 
followed in this direction. They realized what could be 
done with observation and experimentation, and were un- 
willing that any other authority should detennine man's 
thinking. As these men were more and more able to dem- 
onstrate the results of their position, the authority of extra- 
rational processes came into question. This led to an in- 
crease of confidence in the human mind to build its own 
ideas and ihougfrt patterns. la other words, man was de- 
manding the right to think for himself and reach condu- 
it is independently of authority. 

Bacon, Descartes, Spinoza 

This led inevitably to an interest m the processes by 
which man formulates his ideas and the grounds for their 
authority- FBANCK BACOK suggested a method for receiv- 
ing true impressions and building them into true ideas. 
Having cleared the mind of all "idols" or prejudices and 
false points of view, he would have man observe his world 
carefully. As data was collected, Tnan would be in a posi- 
tion to draw conclusions which would have the authority 
of the data upon which they were based. 

To reach a justified conclusion, man must study all inr 
stances in which a certain factor appears, then those in- 
stances in which it does not appear, and then those in- 



IDEAS AND THINKING 25$ 

stances in which it appears with variations of greater or 
less. For example, if one is seeking to discover whether or 
not drinking certain water causes a disease, he would study 
all cases of the disease in which the water was drunlc and 
all cases in which water was not drunk Then he would 
study the amount of the water drunk in each case. On the 
basis of data gathered from these studies, he will be in a 
position to conclude whether or not drinking the water is 
the cause of the disease. 

DESCABTES sought a basis for establishing truth. He rea- 
soned that one must start with premises which cannot be 
denied. Mathematics seemed to give frfrn such premises. 
In mathematics he saw a model for correct thinking, the 
method of reasoning from self-evident truths. This ap- 
peared to him to be the method by which aH true knowl- 
edge could be obtained. Thus he sought first for self-evi- 
dent truths. The one truth which he was able to discover 
was: I thinly therefore I am. With this as a basis, he rea- 
soned to a body of ideas which he did not believe could 
be disputed. These ideas were, for him, dear and distinct, 
and therefore true beyond question. 

Descartes established as a fundamental principle of afl 
thinking that all true ideas must be dear and distinct The 
mind has its norms of dearness and distinctness, norms 
given to the mind because of its nature. Thus, knowledge 
comes to man, Descartes argued, not by sense perception, 
but through careful reasoning from fundamental premises; 
and each idea can be accepted if, after it has been rea- 
soned out, it is dear and distinct 

SPINOZA held that man can have three kmds of knowl- 
edge. Obscure and inadequate ideas, he argued, depend 
upon sense perception, and are the result of the imagina- 
tion plus the failure of the individual to interpret correctly. 
Adequate knowledge, dear and distinct ideas, rational 
knowledge, is the result of reasoning from things already 
known. The third type of knowledge is intuitive knowledge, 
which is the finest kind of knowledge and gives a truth 
which cannot be disputed. Here no error is possible. 



256 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PBOLOSOPHERS 

Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Leibnitz 

JOHN LOCKE made the "study of knowing" his chief oc- 
cupation. His conclusion was that all ideas come to the 
individual through sense experience. The mind is, for him, 
a blank tablet with only the power to assimilate or or- 
ganize impressions. As contact with the environment stim- 
ulates the senses and causes impressions, the mind receives 
and organizes these into ideas and concepts. Thus, there 
are no innate ideas in the mind; all its ideas come from 
without. The ideas which are received through sense im- 
pressions he called simple ideas. As such ideas are organ- 
ized, complex ideas are built up by the mind. 

Locke's writings are concerned in considerable part with 
the classifying of ideas and the study of the power of 
things to produce ideas. 

GEORGB BEBEEXEY went further than Locke did in his 
emphasis on the mind, for he held that we cannot know 
anything beyond what is in the mind. We cannot know 
the material world since we do not have it in our minds. 
Indeed, we cannot prove that the ideas which we have 
are a result of contact with a material world. To account 
for the consistency among ideas, Berkeley held that God 
gives us our ideas. We receive them not from a material 
world, but from God who is mind on a higher level. 

DAVID HUME went still further and held that all we 
have or can know is ideas. We cannot prove the existence 
of a material world or of God. There is just a stream of 
ideas. The mind is this stream of ideas, for him. We re- 
ceive impressions, but do not know from whence they 
come. Then the impressions are organized into ideas. As 
we experience ideas we find that they bear certain rela- 
tions with each other. Thus we get ideas of relations and 
come to the idea, for example, of cause and effect. But we 
cannot say that objects in a material universe are so related. 
All we can say is that ideas follow each other in a certain 
order, and this order we call cause and effect. 

All the contents of the mind are ideas in certain rela- 
tions. Beyond this we cannot go. We -have ideas, and think 



IDEAS AND THINKING 

in terms of them and their relations. Here we must stop. 
We cannot demonstrate anything beyond this. 

LEIBNITZ disagreed with Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, 
by holding that the monad is self-contained and can in no 
way be affected or influenced from the outside. Thus, all 
ideas must be contained within the monad. Experience 
merely brings these ideas to the forefront The senses," he 
wrote, "can arouse, justify, and verify such truths, but 
not demonstrate their eternal and inevitable certitude.* 
Ideas and truths are innate in the mind as tendencies. We 
do not receive ideas, but have them all the time. 

Leibnitz held that Locke had not gone far enough. He 
said that Locke was right in holding that there is nothing 
in the intellect that did not exist before in sensation, but 
that he should add "except the intellect itself.* 

All these later philosophers were attempting to reach a 
satisfactory explanation of how the individual, living in and 
experiencing an environment, could have ideas, thoughts, 
could think* Some had reached the conclusion that the 
individual faced the environment pure and undefiled and 
received his ideas from the environment and through the 
senses. Others had argued that ideas were innate in the 
mind and needed only the stimulation of sensations to bring 
them to consciousness. 

Kant, Fichte, Hegel 

KAJSTT sought to overcome the difficulties of both ex- 
tremes by holding that we do receive impressions from the 
environment, from the *thing-in-itself,* but that the mind 
is of such a nature that it shapes these impressions into 
ideas. The mind, for Inim^ is like a bowl with many crevices 
and strange depressions in its contour. When one pours 
water into the bowl, it takes the shape of the bowl, filling 
all the crevices. In the same way the environment pours 
impressions into the mind and they are received by the 
mind and shaped in accord with the nature of this mind. 

But knowledge is universal. This is due to the fact that 
all minds are fundamentally alike. They all have certain 
fundamental categories such as totality, unity, plurality, 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

reality, and the like. Because all minds are of the same 
general nature, we all think very much alike. We organize 
impressions into ideas. But these are ideas of the mind and 
cannot be applied to a world outside the mind. This leads 
to the conclusion that we cannot know the world outside 
the mind. We can act as though it existed, and can correct 
our ideas in terms of the additional impressions which 
we receive. But beyond this we cannot go. Our ideas are 
a result of the kind of thinking organ which we have, 
and are determined by its nature. 

We can, of course, bring ideas together into large, gen- 
eral ideas, and can act as though these generalizations 
were true. Indeed, to satisfy our moral natures, we must 
so act. But here we are dealing with judgments and not 
provable ideas. 

Kant's masterful argument for the mind as the creator 
erf ideas led FXCBTTE to the conclusion that one can under- 
stand only that which he can create freely in thought. The 
ideas which one has, the contents of one's consciousness, 
are results of an act of creation. The ego, active and free, 
creates everything that man knows, even the "non-ego" or 
that which seems not to be the ego. 

By ego Fidbte means universal reason or intelligence as 
such, not the individual self. Reason, the whole array of 
ideas which one has, is prior to the individual and is the 
creation of a reason which existed before the individual 
man. We know only our ideas. These are not the result of a 
material world which we experience but come from the 
universal ego. 

HEGEL took the position that the processes of the hu- 
man mind and those of nature are the same. In both he 
found what he termed a "dialectical process** operating. 
If one studies the mind, he will find it full of contradictions, 
full of disagreements, of opposites. But, a further study will 
reveal that there is a process in the mind by which each 
pair of opposites is reconciled in a synthesis which includes 
both but on a higher leveL 

This process is everywhere. First there is a thesis or 
affirmation, then we discover the antithesis to this thesis or 



IDEAS AND THINKIKrG 

its contradiction. The highest form of thought is the recon- 
ciling of both in a synthesis which lifts thinking one step 
higher. The human mind does not stop with contradictions, 
but strives to get rid of them by effecting a synthesis. This 
is not to be confused with a compromise. In a true syn- 
thesis the values of both the thesis and the antithesis are 
conserved and together they move toward new values. 

The highest function of the mind, then, is that activity 
which enables one to see things whole, to see opposites 
unified. Here man rises to the true height of his nature. 
Thought moves from the simple ideas to more complex 
notions, from the individual to the rich and fufl. 

Hegel saw what few philosophers had realized to his 
day. He recognized that thought is not a static thing, a 
mere receiving of impressions. Thought, for him, is a proc- 
ess, a moving from one point to another. The thinking 
being is a living logical process in which there is an un- 
folding and a progression. Study of thinking convinced 
Hegel that thinking moves from the simple to the complex 
not by discreet jumps but by a gradual development into 
syntheses which become theses for still higher syntheses. 

But, since nature and thought follow the same process 
of evolution, Hegel reasoned that afl reality is a logical 
process of evolution. The universe is a logical process of 
thought and not dead material upon which thought works. 

This point of view, that everything is a logical process 
of thought obeying the laws of evolution from the simple 
to the more complex, held sway in Germany and influenced 
other countries until the middle of the nineteenth century. 
Indeed, even though it lost some of its popularity after 
that date, it continued to influence world thought for many 
years after. 

A counter influence was the work of HERBAHT who 
looked upon thinking as the organization and integration of 
reals. Through experience the soul throws off reals which 
are organized in consciousness into ideas and points of 
view. Many of these are pushed into the subconscious, 
there to wait until the time is favorable for them to come 
back into consciousness and dominate it. 



260 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHU-OSOPHEBS 

Comte, Mitt, Spencer 

COMTB took the position that the only knowledge worth 
while was knowledge which could be used. He was not 
concerned with theories of knowledge, with attempts to 
discover what knowledge is, but was interested in dis- 
covering knowledge which could be used in actual life 
situations. If one has knowledge, ideas, which work, which 
meet problems and solve them, that is all that is necessary. 
Their source or history is of little or no importance. 

JOHN STOABT MTT.T. based his entire logical theory upon 
the laws of association. He sought to discover how and 
why one passes from the known to the unknown by the 
process of inferences. This became his theory of induction* 
As one collects data through experience, he draws certain 
conclusions. His data serves as a basis for his conclusions. 
"When he goes beyond this data to generalizations he is 
acting upon a belief that nature is uniform. Mill believed 
that man had a right to so act 

Our ideas are a result, then, of experiences and of care- 
ful inferences from them. There are laws, Mill held, by 
which these inferences can be made. These laws have au- 
thority because experience has proved them valuable. Men 
have used them in the past and have arrived at conclusions 
which were successful Therefore, the test of experience 
has been met, and we can afford to make use of them with 
a high degree of confidence. 

HEBBEBT SPENCER held that all thought was founded 
upon the fact of relations. We think in teims of differences 
and likenesses. Our conclusions, our ideas are of these dif- 
ferences and likenesses among things. We know flings in 
terms of their differences and likenesses and not directly. 
Here we have a theory of the relativity of knowledge. Ideas 
are expressions of the relationships between things. 

James and Dewey 

From the theory of knowledge many modem thinkers, 
under the influence of psychological advances of the last 
century, have turned to a study of thinking itself. WIL- 



IDEAS AND THINKING StBl 

JAMES held that thinking is an instrument, and is no 
better than its service in a situation. We think for a pur- 
pose. Thus, James stresses the thinking process, interest in 
how it works and how it can be made more efficient 

JOHN DEWEY has given us one of the dearest analyses 
of reflective thinking ever worked out He identifies refleo- 
tive thinking with problem solving, and holds that man 
does not think unless he has a problem to solve. Mere 
passing fancy, daydreaming, and the like are not thinking 
in any real sense of the term. But, when one is faced with 
a situation for which he does not have a ready solution, he 
engages in thinking. 

Now, the process through which he must go if he is to 
be successful in reaching a solution to his problem consists 
of several fairly well-defined steps. First, there must be a 
clearly defined problem. This is followed by a period dur- 
ing which data relative to the problem is collected. Then, 
on the basis of the data, a hypothesis or possible solution 
is arrived at The fourth step is a mental trying out of the 
suggested solution or hypothesis to discover if there is any 
reason why it should not be the desired solution. If the 
hypothesis stands the test of this mental trial, it is put into 
action, and the results recorded. If this test is also satis- 
factory, the knowledge gained is generalized or applied 
to other similar situations, thus becoming a general prin- 
ciple which may then become a basis for future thought 

All reflective thinking takes place in this fashion, ac- 
cording to Dewey. If each step is carried througji care- 
fully and no mistakes are made, there is a high degree of 
probability that the thinker will arrive at an adequate 
solution of his problem. If, however, any step is neglected 
or the process is not carefully followed, the accepted hy- 
pothesis may prove false. 

Other philosophers hold that Dewey is here considering 
only one type of thinking, and is neglecting the most im- 
portant type, creative thinking. Studies seem to indicate 
that creative thinking proceeds by three stages. First, there 
is a period of preparation during which the thinker studies 
his problem carefully and collects data pertinent to it. Then 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT 1?HILOSOPHEHS 

there must be a period of incubation when this data and 
the problem are put aside, as it were, to become assimi- 
lated. This is, they say, a subconscious process which can- 
not be rushed and the outcome of which cannot be pre- 
dicted. If it is successful, the third stage will reveal itself, 
a stage when the individual experiences iHumination or 
the flash of a possible solution of hypothesis. This hypoth- 
esis is not necessarily the sought-for solution. It must be 
tested both mentally and practically to discover if it is 
adequate. If it fails, the problem must be returned to the 
subconscious and the process of incubation continued* 

Modern philosophy seems to be moving more and more 
in the direction suggested by James and Dewey and other 
Pragmaiists. "While there are many philosophers who are 
struggling with the problem of knowledge and are seeking 
to discover how ideas are formed, the modern spirit of 
efficiency has so dominated many thinkers that they be- 
came impatient with such activity. They can see no real 
value in determining whether ideas are innate or whether 
they come from the outer world. The problems with which 
TTftnf; Fichte, Scheflfng, Herbart; and others struggled, 
seem to them meaningless. Their interest is not in the gene- 
sis of ideas so much as in their working in actual life situa- 
tions. The philosopher, they hold, is concerned with life 
and life situations. Here ideas are tools for solving prob- 
lems* Thinking is a way one may go about meeting difficult 
situations. And its efficiency is to be measured by the suc- 
cess which the individual experiences in its use. If, by 
thinking, he solves his problem, the process has been satis- 
factory and his ideas true. 



Chapter XI 

SOME RECENT APPROACHES TO 
PHILOSOPHY 



KIERKEGAARD HEIDEGGER JASPERS SARTRE 

WHTTEHEAD RUSSELL MOORE CROCE UNAMUNO 

TILLICH NIEBUHR MARTTA3N BUBER 



Why re-examine old concepts and values? Is evil real 
or an illusion? Is there a meaning to suffering? In the 
face of inevitable death, what is the meaning of life? 
Can the findings of science be reconciled with the con~ 
cept of God? What is the function of moral laws in a 
world explained by science? 



From the time of Plato and Aristotle, and even earlier, 
philosophy has been largely concerned with helping man 
to understand the basic, ordered pattern of the universe, 
and man's relationship to man. These two large concerns 
may be described as "metaphysical 5 * and "ethical." In 
some periods philosophers have sought to help men dis- 
cover the meaning of God and in the light of this meaning 
to live lives of goodness and rightness. At other times, 
philosophers have concluded that men could live morally 
without believing in God. All philosophies involve the criti- 
cal analysis of concepts which many people accept in blind 
faith. 

In a changing world, however, old concepts and values 
have to be re-examined. With the increasing importance 
of scientific discovery, many of the traditional ideas about 



284 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHELOSOPEEKS 

tie order of the universe began to change. With increasing 
economic progress and greater material comfort for indi- 
viduals, both spiritual and ethical values have undergone 
subtle changes. In the middle of the nineteenth century, 
many keen thinkers sensed an Inadequacy and inapplica- 
bility in much previous thought The world, for these new 
pMosophers, did not seem to be based on a neat and tidy 
a"bsolute rula The problem of man's existence had to be 
re-examined. New solutions were needed, new answers 
bad to be f oundL 

Kierkegaard and the Beginnings of Existentialism 

S0REN EJEBEEGAAICD, a Danish philosopher and writer, 
took the position that religion was a personal experience. 
Using Kant's idea that the only thing we can TCQOW^ is 
experience as a stepping-oS place, Kierkegaard evolved a 
philosophical system which divided existence into three 
categories; tihat is, lie claimed that experience may be of 
three kinds: aesthetic, ethical, and religious. The child is 
an example of the individual who lives almost exclusively 
at the aesthetic level. For the h*M all choices are made 
in terms of pleasure and pain, and experience is ephemeral, 
having no continuity, no meaning, but being merely a con- 
nection of isolated, non-related moments. The ethical level 
of experience involves choice; whenever conscious choice 
is made, one lives at the ethical level At the religious level, 
one experiences a commitment to oneself, and an aware- 
ness of one's uniqueness and singleness. To live at the re- 
ligious level means to make any sacrifice, any antisocial 
gesture that is required by being true to oneself. Clearly, 
these levels are not entirely separable, but may coexist: 
when (me chooses the aesthetic level of existence, the very 
act of choice involved ethical experience; and when one 
makes choices at the ethical level, and these choices are 
true to one's own singleness, one lives at the religious leveL 

Kierkegaard believed that m^rr proceeding from one 
level of experience to another, would ultimately choose 
suffering and pain, and a constant awareness of the dif- 
ference between ephemeral, temporal existence and ulti- 



SOME RECENT APPROACHES TO PHILOSOPHY 26g 

mate truth. He concluded that only when man experiences 
the suffering of firm commitment to the religious level of 
experience can he be considered to be truly religious, and, 
further, that the suffering endured by God is greater than 
that endured by any man. 

If religion, then, is a purely personal matter, truth is 
clearly subjective, quite separate from the "truth" of re- 
ligious doctrine, for the truth of man's experience must 
emerge from his faithfulness to his own unique identity. 
Kierkegaard recognized this difference between the ob- 
jective, universal truth, and the subjective, personal truth. 
Objective truth, such as that of geometry, is acquired by 
the intellect; subjective truth must be experienced by the 
total individual* One may have objective truth, but one 
must be religious truth. 

The Views of Heidegger, Jaspers, and Sartre 

MARTIN HEIDEGGER, a German, has perceived the mean- 
ingfulness of Kierkegaard's position that man is a tragic 
figure in a finite world. He agreed that man must become 
intensely aware of his own individuality, of the special- 
ness of his own person. In that man, is capable of ques- 
tioning himself, existence precedes essence; that is, mean- 
ing can only be applied to what already is within an 
individual's experience. Man can define kis existence by 
three traits: mood (or feeling), understanding, and sjpeech. 
These traits Heidegger called exktentia&a, and the philo- 
sophic tradition derived from his theories is known as 
"existentialism." Only by questioning existence in terms of 
the existentialia can man become aware of his own true 
identity; and when he has found his identity, the essence 
of his existence, man is able to transcend the limits of the 
non-inquiring world and assert his destiny. 

KARL JASPERS, a German psychologist and philosopher 
and a contemporary of Heidegger, has subscribed to many 
theories of the existential schooL Jaspers* philosophy is 
also centered on the importance of the individual, and he 
has stressed the importance of the discrepancy between 
actual facts and the individual's interpretation of those 



266 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

facts. To Jaspers, truth is subjective, to a large extent non- 
rational, and constantly being reinterpreted by the indi- 
vidual. Freedom, according to Jaspers, is the ability of the 
individual to make spontaneous ethical decisions, and love 
is the highest level of existence. 

Because of the importance of sioffering in existentialism, 
and because of its concern with reconciling man with the 
necessity of death, ft is not surprising that so many twen- 
tieth-century thinkers have been attracted by this philoso- 
phy. Because existentialism is intensely concerned with 
the individual, and with the concrete rather than the ab- 
stract, much of the keenest existential thought has come 
from writers and artists. JEAN-PAUL SARTRE, French play- 
wright and novelist, has developed a philosophy which is, 
in many respects, negative. Yet much of his thought is 
founded on the optimistic principle that "Man is essentially 
a subjectively worthy being/* Sartre recognized the per- 
vasiveness of evil, holding that evil could not be redeemed, 
and that each individual man is responsible for the evil in 
the world. But he also credited man with the capacity for 
heroic action. The ultimate freedom, for Sartre, is the 
freedom to say "No." Man may not be able to overthrow 
evfl, but he can and must refuse to co-operate with evil. 
The freedom to say "No," of course, can only be main- 
tained by total consciousness; and man has, therefore, the 
responsibility to maintain his consciousness both actual 
and spiritual at aH times. Man's existence precedes his 
essence, and from his existence man is free to make of him- 
self what he chooses. 

Three Philosophers of Science: Whitehead, 
Russell, and Moore 

ALFRED NORTH WHTTEHEAD, mathematician and scholar, 
was disturbed by the trend of twentieth-century scientists 
to "prove" with their science the non-existence of God. 
Deeply concerned by this non-religious current in philo- 
sophic thought, he sought to develop a philosophical sys- 
tem in which God and the findings of science would not be 
mutually exclusive or even unharmonious. The theory which 



SOME EECENT APPBOACHES TO PHILOSOPHY 267 

he evolved he called the "philosophy of organism.* White- 
head perceived the relation of man to God in the funda- 
mental processes of the world. He felt that philosophy 
should not start with clear-cut items, but rather with a 
sense of something going on, a process in an unending 
continuum. Just as man's life is made up not of isolated 
units strung together hut of a connected series of minute 
but interrelated moments, Whitehead felt that the world 
is made up of essences and entities which, while undergo- 
ing purely internal development, are nonetheless in active, 
constant contact with each other. It is the interaction of 
these essences throughout nature, and the effects of their 
interrelation as they attempt to adjust to their environment, 
that is the true world process. That the particular world 
we know resulted from the combination of these forces 
in a particular way, instead of the forces having interacted 
differently to produce a different world, is the result of the 
selection and ordering of God. For Whitehead, the ulti- 
mate good is the perception of God as this unifying force 
behind the movement of the world process. Thus White- 
head constructed a metaphysical system which made room 
for the incorporation of all scientific theory and discovery, 
and which included as well aH subjective experience. 

BEBTRANB RUSSELL, originally also a mathematician, 
collaborated with Whitehead on many important early 
projects, though they later disagreed philosophically. Rus- 
sell's approach to mathematics was abstract and formal, 
and he attempted to cast his philosophy in the same mould. 
Russell has emphasized the importance of creativity for 
man, as opposed to activity that is merely acquisitive and 
possessive. Russell came to the conclusion that philosoph/s 
aim is to imderstand the world, and to isolate that which 
may be considered knowledge from all that is merely spec- 
ulative. To do this, man must rely on the scientific method. 
la contrast with many other twentieth-century philoso- 
phers, both Whitehead and Russell agreed on the innate 
dignity and value of man. It was this attitude that pro- 
pelled Russell into the realms of social philosophy in his 



268 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GRKAT PHIIX>SOPHERS 

later years, and his efforts on behalf of various social causes 
have attracted wide attention. 

GEORGE E. MOORE was a neo-realist whose position was 
similar to that of Russell. Moore developed an ethical 
theory which maintained that such words as "good" and 
"right" have no objective meaning, and cannot be recog- 
nized as natural objects scientifically. "Goodness** and 
Brightness" are states or conditions which are simple, un- 
analyzable, and indefinable. 

Logical Positivism 

At the same time that existentialism gained importance 
in world thought and Whitehead's approach to metaphys- 
ical philosophy was claiming wide attention, a philosophic 
school was emerging which was to make radical charges 
against the very nature of philosophy itself. This school 
was "Logical Positivism." Among prominent thinkers in this 
area were LTJDWIG WITTGENSTEIN and the men who es- 
tablished the group known as the "Vienna Circle," Mourns 
SCHLICK and RUDOLF CARNAP. Instead of believing that 
the province of philosophy is to understand the world, they 
believed that its function is the analysis of the uses of lan- 
guage and the properties of sentences. To the logical pos- 
itivists, all knowledge is empirical, and is derived from 
sense experience; that is, all knowledge can be verified 
either by personal experience or by knowing what obser- 
vations would be required in order to verify by personal 
experience. Because there may be an infinite number of 
experiences relevant to the verification of any empirical 
observation, the truth of such observations is at best prob- 
able, and may never be established absolutely. The most 
radical charge of the logical positivists, though, is that the 
statements of metaphysics, theology, and ethics are fac- 
tually meaningless. For example, "Crime is wrong" as a 
sentence makes only one factual, verifiable observation, 
"Crime is." Wrongness, having no existence as an actual, 
observable phenomenon, communicates only a feeling, not 
a fact. Logical positivists claim that such "pseudo-proposi- 
tions" of theology, ethics, and metaphysics are the result 



SOME RECENT APPROACHES TO PHILOSOPHY 269 

of the misunderstanding and misuse of language. Because 
we use the word "God," they say, does not necessarily 
mean that there is a God; and yet, in error, we continue to 
make decisions concerning this non-verifiable concept In- 
evitably, logical positivism, when carried to its extreme 
conclusion, becomes a matter of semantic interpretation 
rather than a creative philosophy. But its impact on twen- 
tieth-century philosophic thought has been profound, and 
its contribution to the clarification of thought and expres- 
sion should not be minimized* 

Two Philosophers of the Spirit 

MiGtoEL I>E UNAMUNO was a Spanish poet, novelist, 
scholar, and philosopher of tremendous originality. His 
entire life was a struggle against the imposition of formal- 
ism upon the individual, and in his writing he constantly 
created new literary forms novels, plays, and poetry 
rather than submit to those established by tradition. Una- 
muno believed that only the internal will of an individual 
is real, and that the external world around hfm is merely 
mist; and, further, that the will of the individual person 
and the spiritual conflicts produced by its passions con- 
tain the final sense of all existence. The basic urge of life, 
thought Unamuno, is not simply to go on living, but to 
grow and to develop. Therefore the fundamental problem 
of life is the necessity of coping with the idea of death, 
which stops all growth. Each man lives in the agony of 
conflict between his wills need for a life after death, and 
his reasons denial of life after death. If one is to exist 
in meaningful terms, one must accept this frustration, and 
in spite of the awareness of death one must will passionate 
action; for even meaningless action, if it is profoundly 
motivated from the inner core of an individual's existence, 
will provide the necessary balance to the twentieth cen- 
tury's stifling, all-pervading dependence on impersonal 
reason. 

BENEDETTO CROCK, an Italian critic and historian, con- 
cerned himself largely with problems of aesthetics. Croce 
took the position that the spirit is the only reality, though 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

it manifests itself in various different guises in the external 
world, a concept similar to that developed by Whitehead. 
Croce extended this idea by maintaining that the physical 
does not exist at afl, but is merely a construction of the 
mind. For example, a work of art is an image created in 
the mind of the artist and communicated to the minds of 
the audience. Only the image is a work of art; the physical 
objectpainting, piece of sculpture, or other form is 
merely a practical act to aid reproduction of the image. 
This concept is of great importance in the understanding 
of much modern art 

Some Current Philosophers in the Religious Tradition 

Although much of contemporary philosophy has implied 
a negation of the concept of God, many twentieth-century 
philosophers have found themselves closer to the tradi- 
tional religious points of view. They recognize the need for 
a new set of moral values as well as do the agnostics in 
the philosophical fraternity, but they believe that such 
values <^n be found by a re-examination and a redefini- 
tion of religious principles. 

PAUL THXICH, a German Protestant theologian, sees a 
true "God above the God of Theism.* Man is beset by 
anxiety over the inevitability of physical death, but he has 
the responsibility to accept this anxiety, to take it upon 
himself. In so doing, he achieves transcendence. For Til- 
lich, religion is man's striving for the ultimate, the abso- 
lute. There can be no atheistic society, since striving for 
any absolute is, by definition, religious activity, and the 
point of a society's existence is to strive toward a goal. In 
spite of a possible lack of meaning in existence, faith con* 
stitutes acceptance of what is given. 

REINHOLD NIKBUHK, an American Protestant theologian, 
abjured the traditional liberal Protestant point of view 
that man is essentially good. On the contrary, according to 
Niebuhr, only God is good, and man is beset by sin. Man's 
only hope for salvation is to rely on the goodness of GocL 

JACQUES MABITAIN, a neo-TTiomistic French Catholic, 
reconciled existential philosophy with the Thomistic tra- 



SOME BECENT APPROACHES TO PHELOSOPHY 

dition. To Maritain, all forms of knowledge scientific, 
metaphysical, and mystical are valid. 

MARTIN BUBER, oriented in traditional Jewish values, 
has expressed the view that man was made less than hu- 
man by the encroachments of science and mechanization. 
With the increase of dehumanization in the world, evil in- 
creases; and as men lose their identities, they lose their 
souls. To counteract this evil, Buber proposed his Ich itnd 
Du philosophy: Ich, the German word for "I" points out 
the importance of recognizing one's own individuality, 
one's own uniqueness; Du 9 the personal form of "you," 
emphasizes that the individuals one encounters must be 
loved and absorbed into one's own identity. But a general- 
ized love of mankind is not enough; one must recognize the 
subjectivity of other people; and only when there is a har- 
monious balance within an individual of an awareness of 
his own self and an awareness of and love for the unique- 
ness of the selves of others can the individual find fulfill- 
ment and contentment 

As conditions change and man's environment becomes 
different, the mind of man must construct new philosophies 
for new times. What Plato and Aristotle did for their 
times, the thinkers of these recent days have done for 
theirs. And the mind of the philosopher, ever alert and 
sensitive to change, will continue to meet the challenges 
of the future as they arise. 



CONCLUSION 



One's experience, whether it be yours or mine or that of 
a Great Philosopher, may be thought of as many pieces of 
a jig-saw puzzle. The pieces are scattered everywhere in 
time and space. Some date back to earliest childhood while 
others are now ia the process of being born. Some are the 
result of events far out near the horizon, while others are 
within erne's own body. Often they have baffling shapes. 
Each one of us attempts to fit the pieces which are our 
experiences together so that they will form a picture that 
satisfies us. 

You and I wffl often try to force pieces together when 
they are not made to fit in the way we desire. We wiH 
push and shove the pieces until the spaces between them 
are as small as possible. In doing this, we often force them 
out of shape. Thus, the final picture will be full of gaps 
which we may not be able to see but which are obvious to 
another of more experience and a keener insight and under- 
standing. It wffl contain shocking contrasts of color. It will 
be smaH and incomplete. 

Although the picture which you and I build may be 
adequate for most of the practical situations in. which we 
find ourselves, there will come times of crisis when it will 
not prove adequate. A new experience may not fit into 
the picture at alL At such times we may try to rearrange 
the pieces so as to make a place for the new experience 
and thus fashion a very different picture, or we may throw 
the piece away, saying that it is an "unreal" experience, 
false, an illusion. 

The experiences which a Great Philosopher employs to 



CONCLUSION 273 

weave his pattern, his philosophy, are far more numerous 
than ours. He attempts to include the entire universe, all 
that there is, in the picture which he constructs. Further, 
he is constantly on the alert to discover gaps, delicate 
shadings, fine cuts of the pieces with which he works. He 
trains his mind to a high degree of sensitivity to these 
differences. He can detect errors in the relationships be- 
tween pieces which escape the less trained mind. Thus, 
the picture which he presents to the world is more accurate 
and complete than ouis. 

But even the Great Philosopher does not fashion a per- 
fect picture. Only a God who knows all experiences of all 
men and can detect the finest relations can weave a perfect 
pattern. No philosopher, however great, is such a God. 
Thus the pattern of every Great Philosopher is imperfect 
and subject to improvement. 

The history of philosophy is the story of how different 
philosophers have woven different patterns, proposed dif- 
ferent solutions to the puzzle that is human experience. 
One philosopher will offer his solution and many will hail 
it as the answer. But it will not be long before another 
philosopher will discover and point to errors in his pattern, 
will reveal gaps and distortions, and will propose a some- 
what different solution, one which seems to him more 
nearly perfect He, in turn, will be followed by another 
who repeats the process. 

In the pages which constitute this book we have seen 
how many Great Philosophers have attempted to piece 
together the world of human experience and have sought 
to answer some of the problems which have often inter- 
ested us. We have seen how each Has given a somewhat 
different answer and how later philosophers have corrected 
them and offered other solutions. 

Thus, in a real sense, you and I can stand on the shoul- 
ders of all the Great Philosophers of the past As we too 
look out upon the world, *we can build our philosophies 
with the benefit of their experience and advice. We can 
learn from them, and by learning can make our picture 
more accurate and complete. Each philosopher says to us, 



2/4 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHTLOSQPHEBS 

**Here is what the universe of human experience means to 
me, and here are the mistakes which I have found in the 
other philosophers who have preceded me. This is the best 
I know. Take it and begin your thinking from here.** 

You and I stand at the apex of centuries of struggling 
with the great problems of mankind. Behind us are great 
minds who offer us the service of their experience and 
thought. Indeed, we should be greater philosophers than 
any of the past since we have all the past to help us. Let 
us, then, consider what these of the past tell us. Let us 
ponder their advice carefully. And let us carry on from 
where they have had to stop. This is the way to progress 
and to a more perfect philosophy. 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 



ABELABD, PETER: (1079-1142). Bora at Palais, near 
Nantes, in Brittany. Opened a school in Paris in 1103 
and became noted for his keen mind and theological pene- 
tration. Among his more important writings are Ethics and 
Introduction to Theology. 

ALCUIN: (735-804) . An English theologian and scholar. 
He was called from York to assist Charlemagne in es- 
tablishing an educational system in the Prankish Empire. 
In his old age he retired to the monastery at Tours and 
devoted himself to theology. 

ALTHUSIUS, JOHANNES: (1557-1638). A German thinker 
who is credited with founding the modern theory of nat- 
ural law. He was born at Diedenshausen, studied at Baste 
and Geneva, and became Professor of Law at Herbort 
Among his significant writings is Political Method. 

AMBROSE, ST.: (34O?-3Q7). Born at Treves and became 
Bishop of Milan in 374. He often came into conflict with 
the highest authorities of his times. He wrote the great 
Christian hymn, **Te Deum Laudamus/* 

ANAXAGOKAS: (sooP-4^8 B.C.)* Born at Clazomenae. 
After traveling widely he settled in Athens and opened a 
philosophic school there. Many famous thinkers studied 
with him. He was condemned to die for alleged impiety, 
but the sentence was changed to exile. He retired to Lamp- 
sacus and taught philosophy there until his death. 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHELOSOPHERS 

ANAXIMANBER: (6n?-547? B.C.). Famous both as 
mathematician and as philosopher. He taught that the 
moon received her light from the sun and that the earth 
was round. He believed in the existence of many worlds. 

ANASIMENES OF MILETUS: (6th cent B.C.)- A Greek 
philosopher. He believed that the basic substance of the 
universe was air, from which everything else derives by 
rarefaction or condensation* 

ANSELM, ST.: (1033-1109). He was Archbishop of Can- 
terbury during the reigns of William Rufus and Henry I. 
He was a man of great piety and intellectual power and 
resisted efforts of the king to despoil the church of her dig- 
nity and revenue. 

AQTJOTAS, THOMAS: (i225?-i274) Known as the "An- 
gelic Doctor." He was descended from the counts of Aquino 
in Calabria. In 1323 Pope John XXII made him a saint 
His writings form the basis for the Thomist sect Several 
editions of his Selected Writings are available. 

ABISTOTLE: (384-322 B.C.)- Born at Stagira in Thrace. 
Began his study with Plato when he was 20 years of age. 
Philip of Macedon made Mm tutor to his son, Alexander 
the Great. He was accused of impiety and exiled to Chalcis 
where he died. Among his many important writings are 
The Nicomachean Ethics and Politics. 

ATHANASIUS: (2gs?-373). Born in Egypt, entered the 
church at an early age, and became Bishop of Alexandria 
in 326. He was violently opposed to Arisu and the Arian 
position and often came into conflict with the authorities. 

AUGUSTINE, AUBEUUS: (354-43 ) Born at Tagaste in 
Africa. He became Bishop of Hippo and wrote with great 
force against all he deemed as heretics. Among his most 
famous works are the Confessions and City of God. 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 2/7 

BACON, FRANCIS: (1561-1626). Born in London. He 
rose to great heights in the English government and be- 
came lord chancellor. But his venality as a judge caused 
his downfall and imprisonment After he was pardoned by 
the king, he retired to his studies. The Advancement of 
Learning is one of his more famous works. 

BACON, ROGER: (i2i4?-i2g4). An English scientist and 
publicist. He is reputed to have invented gunpowder and 
to have manufactured magnifying glasses. 

BASEDOW, JOHANN BERNHABD: (1724-1790). A German 
educator and teacher who attempted to work out the doc- 
trines of Rousseau in an educational system. He wrote sev- 
eral books for children. 

BAYLE, PIERRE: (1647-1706). Applied Descartes* 
method to the dogmatism of his day and effected reforms 
in thinking. 

BENEDICT, ST.: (4807-543?) . Born at Nursia, in the 
Duchy of Spoleto. He established the famous monastery of 
Monte Cassino near Naples in 529 and founded the first 
religious order in the West, the Benedictine order. 

BENTHAM, JEREMY: (1748-1832). A distinguished Eng- 
lish writer on political economy and jurisprudence. Among 
his writings is the well-known Fragment on Government. 

BERGSON, HENRI: (1859-1941). Born in Paris. Was one 
of the great modern French philosophers and received 
many honors from the French government He became a 
member of the French Academy in 1914. He held several 
important chairs of philosophy in France. Among his ex- 
tensive writings are Matter and Memory 9 Introduction to 
Metaphysics, and Creative Evolution. 

BERKELEY, GEORGE: (1685-1753). A famous English 
divine. Born in Ireland and educated at Trinity College, 



2/8 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

Dublin. He conceived a plan for converting America to 
Christianity and set out for the Bermudas to erect a college 
there, but the project failed because the money which he 
expected did not come. In 1734 he was made Bishop of 
Cloyne. Prominent among his works are A New Theory of 
Vision and Principles of Human Knowledge. 

BODIN, JEAN: (1530-1596). A French jurist. For a time 
he enjoyed the favor of Henry III, but later forfeited it by 
defending the rights of the classes and the masses against 
the king. He was closely allied with the group known as 
the "Politicians" in France. 

BOEHME, JACOB: (1575-1624). An uneducated German 
cobbler who became famous because of his mystical ex- 
periences and his writings dealing with mysticism. One of 
his important works is The Signature of All Things. 

BRADLEY, FEANCIS HERBERT: (1846-1924). Born in 
Glasbury in England and educated at Oxford. Made a fel- 
low of Merton College where he lived for his entire life. He 
is the author of Appearance and Reality. 

BRUNO, GIORDANO: (i548?-i6oo). A member of the 
Dominican order. He left the order and wandered through- 
out the world, at last returning to Italy where he was im- 
prisoned by the Inquisition and burned at the stake. 

BUBER, MARTIN: (1878-1965). Bom in Vienna, Buber 
was raised in the Orthodox Jewish tradition. Intensely in- 
terested in Zionism, he escaped from Nazi Germany, where 
he had been teaching, to Palestine, in 1938. He was among 
the first of the former German citizens to resume cultural 
relations with Germany by accepting the Goethe Prize in 
1951. One of his most important books is I and Thou. 

CAMPANELLA, TOMMASO: (1568-1639). A Dominican 
monk who was persecuted by the Inquisition. He spent 27 



BIOGRAPHICAJL NOTES 2/9 

years of his life in prison for ideas which he never at- 
tempted to put into practice. City of the Sun is one of his 
major works. 

CARNAP, RUDOLF: (1891-1970). Bom in Germany. 
While an instructor at the University of Vienna, he joined 
Schlick in founding logical positivism in the 1920*5. In 
1936, he came to the United States, where he was a 
professor of philosophy at the University of Chicago and at 
the University of California. His writings are par- 
ticularly concerned with semantics. Published works in- 
clude Introduction to Semantics and Logical Foundations 
of 'Probability. 

CABNEADES: (213-129 B.C.) . The greatest skeptic of the 
Academy established by Plato. 

CICERO, MARCUS TUIXIUS: (106-43 B.C.). Born in AT- 
pinum. A Roman orator and statesman. He held many high 
offices in Rome, fought conspirators, and was eventually 
murdered by emissaries of Mark Antony. His philosophical 
works are available in several editions. One of his most imr 
portant works is On Orators and Oratory. 

CLEMENT OF AT.KXANPBIA; (i5o?-22O?). An early 
Christian theologian, he was one of the first to attempt to 
reconcile Platonic and Christian thought. With his famous 
pupil Origen, he helped make Alexandria a great center of 
learning. Among his surviving works are Address to the 
Greeks and Who Is the Eich Mart? Who Is Saved? 

COMENIUS, JOHN AMOS: (1592^1670). A great Moravian 
educator and leader of the religious life of the Moravians. 
He was persecuted violently but continued in his faith and 
his educational endeavors. He advocated the "method of 
nature" in teaching. 

COMTE, AUGUSTE: (1798-1857). Born in MontpeDier, 
France, and attended the polytechnic school at Paris. He 



S.8Q BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHELQSOPHEBS 

was well versed in the exact sciences and in mathematics. 
Among Ms interesting writings is Positive Philosophy. 

CROCE, BENEDETTO: (1866-1952). An Italian historian 
and critic, Croce devoted his life almost exclusively to 
studying and writing. He was a senator, and later became 
minister of education. Firmly opposed to Fascism, Croce 
emerged from retirement in 1943 to become the leader of 
Italy's Liberal Party. He is the author of Philosophy of the 
Spirit, which is the work presenting his system. 

COMBEBLAND, RiCHABD: (1631-1718). An English phi- 
losopher and churchman. His belief in the principle of uni- 
versal benevolence opposed him to Hobbes's egoism and 
led to his being considered the founder of utilitarianism. 
Principal work: On Natural Law. 

DEMOCBTTUS: (460-370 B.C.) . Born at Abdera in Thrace. 
He traveled widely and wrote many books on science, phi- 
losophy, and mathematics. 

DESCAJRTES, REN; (1596-1650). Born in the Touraine, 
France. Was a soldier and served the armies of the Dutch 
and the Bavarians. He settled in Holland and there wrote 
many books which had wide influence throughout the en- 
tire world. Among the most significant of these are A Dis- 
course on Method and Meditations on the First Philosophy. 

DKWKY, JOHN: (1859-1952). An outstanding American 
philosopher. Born in Vermont He wrote widely on phi- 
losophy, education, psychology, political science. Through 
his writings and lectures he influenced the processes of 
thought throughout the world. Among his influential works 
are Democracy and Education, Experience and Nature, 
and Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. 

ECKHABT, MEISTEK: (ia6o?-i3^7?). A German mystic. 
Member of the Dominican order. Taught and wrote widely 
and had great influence as a minister. 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 28l 

EMPEDOCLES: (495?~435? B.C.). Born in Agrigentum, 
Sicily, the son of a wealthy and public-spirited family. He 
was a leader of the democratic elements in his city, and is 
said to have refused the kingship. He was likewise a re- 
ligious teacher, poet, and physician. He believed that he 
possessed powers of magic. 

EPICURUS: (342?-~27o B.C.) . Born on the island of Samos 
of Athenian parents. He taught in many Greek cities and 
founded a school at Athens where he lived the remainder 
of his life. His complete Extant Writings axe available. 

ERIGENA, JOHN SCOTTJS: (8i5?-877?). Born in Ireland 
and educated in Irish schools. Was called by Charles the 
Bald to head the Schola Palatina at Paris. One of his more 
important works is On the Division of Nature. 



FlCHTE, JOHANN GOTTLIEB; (1762-1814). Bom HI 

ony, the son of a poor weaver. Received his education 
through the generosity of a rich nobleman and rose to 
fame as a teacher of philosophy and a writer. Was one of 
the founders of the University of Berlin, Among his writings 
are Science of Ethics and Science of Rights. 

FKOEBEL, FRIEDRICH WTT.HKT/M AUGUST: (1782^1852). 
Born in a small village in the Thuringian forest Attended 
the University of Jena and met and studied under some of 
the greatest minds of his times. Founded the first kinder- 
garten. 

GALILEO, G.: (1564-1642). Born in Pisa and educated 
at Florence* Studied medicine and mathematics. Became 
famous as an astronomer and invented the first telescope. 
He came into conflict with the Inquisition but was able to 
escape death when he promised not to teach that the sun 
was the center of the universe. 

GREEN, THOMAS HILL: (1836-1882). Born in Birldn, 
Yorkshire. The son of the rector of the parish. Became 



282 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

student at Oxford where he spent the remainder of his life 
as student and teacher. Was widely interested in educa- 
tion. Had great faith in the common people and in democ- 
racy. 

GROTIUS, HUGO: (1583-1645) . Leader of the aristocratic 
party in Holland. Born at Delft. Spent most of his life in 
public office and was several times in conflict with the 
authorities. Became the Swedish ambassador to Paris in 
1635 where he remained until shortly before his death. 
One of his chief works is The Law of War and Peace. 

HAMILTON, SIR WILLIAM: (1788-1856). Scottish phi- 
losopher. Taught at the University of Edinburgh. He left 
his library to the University of Glasgow, 

HABTLEY, DAVCD: (1705-1757). An English physician 
and philosopher, he founded associational psychology, 
which holds that the whole mind does not represent a 
*souT but is the result of the many different sensations im- 
pinging upon it His principal work is Observations on 
Man. 

HEGEL, GEOBG WTT.HKT/NC FRIEDRICH: (1770-1831)* 
Born in Stuttgart and studied theology and philosophy at 
Tubingen. Served as professor at a number of the great 
seats of learning such as Jena, Heidelberg, and Berlin. 
Among his many literary works are Phenomenology of 
Mind, Logic, and Philosophy of Right. 

HEIDEGGER, MABTIN: (1889-1976). A German philoso- 
pher, he was professor at the University of Marburg 
(1923-28) and at the University of Berlin (1928-^33). He 
is generally regarded as the father of atheistic existential- 
ism. Among his writings is Existence and Being. 

HEBACLTTDS: (535?-475? B.C.). Born in Ephesus. Was 
an aristocrat and had no respect for democracy. He was 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 283 

called "The Obscure" because his writings were hard to 
understand. 

HEBBABT, JOHANN FBIEDBICH: (1776-1841). A critical 
German thinker who opposed the entire Idealistic move- 
ment He held many famous chairs of philosophy, includ- 
ing the one made famous by Kant at Konigsberg, 

HESIOD: (8th cent? B.C.) . Greek poet of whom virtually 
nothing is known. Possibly a Boeotian fanner, his works 
include Works and Days. 

HOBBES, THOMAS: (1588-1679). Studied Scholasticism 
and the philosophy of Aristotle at Oxford and traveled 
widely on the continent where he met many of the great 
minds of his day. After the assembling of the Long Parlia- 
ment he fled to France in November, 1640, and did not 
return until he made his peace with Cromwell in 1651, 
His writings include Leviathan, Of Liberty and Necessity, 
and On Human Nature* 

HOLBACH, PAUL HENBI THIRY, BARON D': (1723-1789). 
A French philosopher, one of the Encyclopedists, An op- 
ponent of organized religion, he believed that man is in- 
nately moral though perverted by society.. His principal 
work is System of Nature. 

HUME, DAVID: (1711-1776). Born in Edinburgh. Stud- 
ied law and became Under-Secretary of State in 1767. His 
fame during his lifetime rested upon his ability as an his- 
torian. Among his most important works are Treatise of 
Human Nature, Philosophical Essays, and Inquiry Con- 
cerning Human Understanding. 

HUTCHESON, FRANCIS: (1694-1746). A professor of phi- 
losophy at the University of Glasgow from 1729. Hutehe- 
son was an early utilitarian, believing that of man's many 
senses, the most important is the moral. He was also one 



284 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

of the first to write on the subject of aesthetics. Among his 
works is the System of Moral Philosophy. 

JAMES, WILLIAM: (1842-1910). Born in New York 
City. He was educated in private schools and by tutors in 
New York, attended the Lawrence Scientific School and 
was graduated from the Harvard Medical School in 1869. 
His teaching career included anatomy, physiology, psy- 
chology, and philosophy. He taught at Harvard University, 
University of Edinburgh, and at Oxford. Among his many 
significant writings are Pragmatism, The Meaning of Trvth> 
and Essays in Radical Empiricism, 

JASPEBS, KABL: (1883-1969). A German philosopher 
and psychologist, he taught philosophy at the University 
of Heidelberg. One of Germany's leading philosophers, he 
was associated with the existential movement. Two of his 
provocative books are Man in the Modern Age and The 
Question of German Guilt. 

KANT, IMMANUEL: (1724-1804)* Born at Konigsberg, 
the son of a saddler. Nearly his entire life as student, 
teacher, and writer was spent in the town of his birth. His 
writings influenced the trends of thought as much as those 
of any philosopher who ever lived. The large body of his 
written works includes the Critique of Pure Reason, the 
Critique of Practical Reason, and the Critique of Judg- 
ment. 

KIEBKEGAAKD, S0BEN: (1813-185$). A Danish philoso- 
pher and writer on religious subjects. He had a profound 
effect on Danish literature as the result of his writings on 
aesthetics. Many of his ideas were incorporated into ex- 
istentialism. His writings include Stages on Life's Way and 
The Gospel of Suffering and The Lilies of the Field. 

LA METTRIE: (1709-1751). The founder of French ma- 
terialism. For some time he was a military doctor but lost 
his position because of his materialistic views. He was 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES ^8$ 

hounded and persecuted and is believed to have died from 
poisoning. 

LEIBNITZ, GOTTFBJED WELHELM: ( 1646-1716). Born int 
Leipzig and studied law, philosophy, and mathematics at 
Jena. He received his doctorate in law at the age of 20. He 
served as court councilor and librarian at Hanover until 
his death. Various editions of his Philosophical Writings 
are available* 



(sth cent B.C.). Little is known of his life. 
He is said to have come from Miletus and to have studied 
with Zeno at Elea. He possibly established the school at 
Abdera which Democritus made famous. 

LOCKE, JOHN: (1632-1704). He studied philosophy, 
natural science, and medicine at Oxford. For many years 
he was in the service of the Earl of Shaf tesbury as secretary 
and tutor to his son and grandson. He followed his patron 
in exile to Holland and returned to England with the rise of 
William of Orange, He is the author of On CM Gooern- 
ment. 

LOTZE, RTOOLF HERMANN: (1817-1881). Studied med- 
icine and philosophy at Leipzig and became a teacher of 
physiology and philosophy at that university* He also 
taught at Gottingen and at Berlin. 

LTJTHEB, MABTIN: (1483-1546). The leader of the Ref- 
ormation. While teaching at Wittenberg he challenged the 
church and was from then on the center of the rebellion 
against church authority. His written works have been col- 
lected several times. 

MACHIAVELLI, NICCOL&: (1469-1527). An Italian dip- 
lomat. Secretary of the Council of Ten at Florence. In 
later years he was exiled by the MedicL His most famous 
book is The Prince. 



286 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

MAISTRE, JOSEPH DE: (1753-1821). French writer and 
diplomat in the service of Sardinia. His great literary skill 
made his opposition to the French Revolution widely and 
effectively felt. He believed the world should be ruled en- 
tirely by the pope, with no separate civil authorities. His 
works include On the Pope and Discussions in St. Peters- 
burg. 

MAIJEBRANCHE, NICOLAS: (1638-1715). A member of 
the Oratory of Jesus. He sought to harmonize religion and 
philosophy, the position of Descartes and that of Augustine, 
but failed so that his works were put on the Index. 

MARITAIN, JACQUES: (1882-1973). Raised a Protes- 
tant, he became dissatisfied with the values of his upbring- 
ing, and joined the Catholic Church in 1906 in his native 
France. Strongly interested in the writings of St. Thomas 
Aquinas, Maritain developed and integrated Thomistic 
principles with everyday life. From 1945 to 1948 he was 
French Ambassador to the Vatican. Among his important 
works are An Introduction to Philosophy and Art and 
Scholasticism. 

MAHX, KJLRL: (1818-1883). Born in Treves, Germany. 
Widely recognized as the foremost Socialist philosopher 
and founder of the international Socialist movement. 

Mnx, JOHN STUABT: (1806-1873). Son of James Mill, 
secretary in the East India Company. His father gave him 
a special education consisting of much training in philos- 
ophy and political science. He also served with the East 
India Company, and later entered Parliament as a liberal. 
Some of his most significant books are On Liberty, Repre- 
sentative Government, and Utilitarianism. 

MILTON, JOHN: (1608-1674), English poet and philos- 
opher. He studied at St. Paul's School and at Cambridge. 
He was appointed foreign secretary to the Council of State 
in 1649 and later, because of much careful work, became 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 287 

blind. His writings are English classics, One of his most 
important philosophical works is Tractate of Education. 

MOORE, GEORGE E.: (1873-1958). An English philos- 
opher, he was professor at Cambridge University. He also 
was a guest lecturer at many colleges and universities in 
the United States from 1940 to 1944. A neorealist, his posi- 
tion is similar to that of Bertrand RusselL Philosophical 
Studies is one of his chief works. 

NEWTON, SIR ISAAC; (1642-1727). Born at Wools- 
thorpe in Lincolnshire and educated at Cambridge where 
he studied mathematics. He made many scientific discov- 
eries and was honored highly by the English government 

NICHOLAS OF CUSA: (i4Oi?-i464). Though a Ro- 
man Catholic prelate and cardinal from 1448, Nicholas 
was a humanist and had an original and critical mind. In 
1451, he was made papal legate and traveled widely, 
preaching and reforming monasteries. But his reforms were 
not carried through. He anticipated Copernicus in believ- 
ing that the earth orbits the sun. 

NEEBUHR, REINHOIJ>: (1892-1971). An American the- 
ologian, he spent the early years of his ministry as pastor 
of a church in Detroit, where many of his parishioners 
were automobile workers with whom he sided in their 
struggles for better working conditions. A liberal in politics, 
he adjured many of the liberal theological tenets. 
Among his many important writings are Moral Man and 
Immoral Society, The Nature and Destiny of Man, and 
Beyond Tragedy. 

NIETZSCHE, FBIEDBICH WTT.HKT.M: (1844-1900). A dis- 
tinguished German philosopher, born at Rocken near Leip- 
zig. Became a professor of classical philology at Basle. Per- 
haps his most famous book is Thus Spake Zamthustra. 

OBIGEN: (i85?-*54?). A Christian apologist, scholar, 
and theologian; bom in Egypt. At age eighteen, Origen be- 



288 BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

came head of the famous catechetical school of Alexandria, 
having previously studied under Clement of Alexandria. 
Later, Origen established his own school at Caesarea. He 
is reputed to have written 800 works, and he became fa- 
mous for his exegesis of the scriptures. Among his surviving 
works are Commentaries, Homilies, and Against Celsus. 

PAHACEI-SUS: (1493?-! 541). His real name was Theo- 
phrastus of Hohenheim. A leading figure among a group of 
"wonder men'* of the period, men who worked miracles. 

PAHMENIDES: ($th cent. B.C.). The son of a wealthy 
Elean family who developed the philosophy of Xenophanes, 
He was probably a Pythagorean in his early days. 

PASCAL, BLAISE: (1623-1662). A gifted mathematician 
and physicist He was also influenced by mysticism and 
sought to combine a mystic religious point of view with 
the findings of mathematics and science. 

PAULSEN, FRIEDBICH: (1846-1908). A German philos- 
opher who presented an idealistic world-view similar to 
that of Lotze and Fechner. He was widely read in both 
Germany and the United States. 

PELAGIUS: (36o?-42O?). A celebrated British monk and 
theologian. His opposition to Augustinian doctrines of pre- 
destination and total depravity led to his persecution and 
banishment from Rome in 418. A heretical sect (Pelagian- 
ism) grew from his teachings on the perfectibility of man. 
He is the author of On the Trinity, On Free Witt, and 
Commentary on P&uFs Epistles. 

PESTAIAXZZI, JOHANN HEINBICH: (1746-1827). Born at 
Zurich. He was inspired to relieve the suffering of the 
peasantry about htm and made many attempts to educate 
them and give them better methods of fanning and living. 
His influence on modern education has been wide and deep. 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 

PHILO: (20? B.a~go? A.D.). Known as "the JeV or "of 
Alexandria." He came of a priestly family and wrote widely 
on historical, political, and ethical matters. He held that 
Judaism was the sum-total of human wisdom. 

Pi*AT0: (427?-Q47? B.C.) . Bom the son of noble parents. 
The greatest pupil of Socrates* He traveled widely, had an 
independent income, and lived in the highest of style. He 
was intimate with Dionysius I, the tyrant of Syracuse, and 
is said to have hoped to establish an ideal state at Syracuse, 
He founded the Academy in a grove outside of Athens. His 
extant writings are almost all included in the famous Dia- 
logues (of which the Republic is one). 

PLOTINUS: (2O5?-27o). Born in Lycopolis, Egypt. 
Studied philosophy under Ammonius Saccas in Alexandria 
for eleven years. He established a school in Rome soon after 

343* 

PRIESTUEY, JOSEPH: (1733-1804). A Unitarian natural 
philosopher. He made great discoveries concerning the 
properties of fixed air. His sympathies with the French 
Revolution resulted in his house being wrecked by a mob. 
After this he fled to the United States and remained here 
until his death. 

PROTAGORAS: (sth cent. B.C.). A famous Sophist, he 
taught in Athens and was a friend of Pericles. His agnos- 
ticism caused his banishment from Athens. He was con- 
sidered the first to systematize grammar, distinguishing 
parts of speech, teases, and moods. One of his most noted 
works is On the Gods. 

PYTHAGORAS: (580-500 B.C.). Born in Samos and emi- 
grated to the Greek colonies in Southern Italy about 55219. 
He founded the school of the Pythagoreans, a semi-reli- 
gious and philosophic sect 



29O BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 

QCXNTHJCAK: (35?-95?)- A Roman rhetorician whose 
work had great influence in antiquity and in the Renais- 
sance. Among his more famous writings is Institutes of 
Oratory. 



RAMOS, PfcTRUS; (1515-157*) H& true French name 
was Pierre de la Ramee. He was influenced by Vives and 
attacked the Aristotelian logic as responsible for the barren 
dialectical methods used in the universities of his time. He 
attempted to establish a new logic. He was also influential 
as an educator. 

REID, THOMAS: (1710-1796). Leader of the Scottish 
school in its reaction against the idealism of Berkeley and 
the skepticism of Hume, He attempted to return to "com- 
mon sense" in philosophy. 

RQSGELJN: (fl. 1092-1119). Scholastic philosopher. He 
was a canon at Loches and taught Abelard. Considered 
the founder of nominalism. He was forced to recant his 
doctrine of the Trinity by a council at Soissons. 

ROUSSEAU, JEAN JACQUES: (1712^-1778). French phi- 
losopher, political theorist, and writer whose colorful and 
scandalous life has led to many conflicting theories about 
his personality. Among his more important philosophical 
writings are Emile and The Social Contract. 

ROYCE, JOSIAH: (1855-1916). Born in Grass Valley, Cali- 
fornia. Studied at the University of California and at Leip- 
zig, Gottingen, and Johns Hopkins. Though he taught 
English for a while at the University of California, he spent 
most of his teaching years as professor of Philosophy at 
Harvard University. The Spirit of Modern Philosophy and 
The World and the Individual are among his major works. 

RUSSELL, BERTHAKD: (1872-1970)* Bom at Trefleck, 
Monmouth, England, and educated at Trinity College, 
Cambridge. He lectured widely and received many 
high honors for scholarship. In 1950 he received the Nobel 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 

Prize for Liteiature. Among his extensive works are History 
of Western Philosophy and Human Knowledge. With Al- 
fred North Whitehead he wrote the monumental Prindpfo 
Mathematica. 

SAINT-SIMON, CLAUDE HENBI BE ROUVROT, COMTE I>E: 
(1760-1825). French political scientist who conceived the 
idea of a new society in which there would be equal distri- 
bution of property, power, culture, and happiness. 

SANTAYANA, GEORGE: (1863-1952) . Born in Madrid and 
graduated from Harvard University. He taught philosophy 
at Harvard for twenty-two years. Then, from 1912 on, he 
lived principally in Europe. In 1943 he was elected an 
honorary member of the American Academy of Arts and 
Letters. He was a poet and literary critic, as well as a 
philosopher. He died in Italy. His many important works 
include The Realm of Essence and Scepticism and Animal 
Faith. 

SARTRE, JEAN-PAUL: (1905-1980). French novelist and 
playwright, he is considered the founder of French exis- 
tentialism. He was imprisoned by the Germans during the 
early part of World War II, and upon his escape he joined 
the resistance movement in Paris. Both his philosophical 
writings and his plays and novels have received interna- 
tional attention and acclaim. Perhaps his philosophy is 
best stated in Being and Nothingness. 

SCHEIXING, FRIEDRICH WILHELM JOSEPH: (17751854), 
Studied theology at Tubingen and became professor of 
philosophy at Jena in 1798. He became one of the brilliant 
circle in which the Romantic movement centered. He was 
called to Berlin to stem the tide of Hegelian philosophy, but 
met with little success. Prominent among his major works 
are Of Human Freedom and Transcendental Idealism. 

SCHT .EDERMACHER, FRIEDRICH ERNST DANIEL: (1768- 

1834), Bom in Breslau and received part of his education 
in the schools of the Moravian brotherhood. After a short 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHTLOSOPHEBS 

stay as student and tutor at Halle, he went to Berlin as 
minister of Trinity Church. Later he became professor of 
theology at the University of Berlin. 

SCTUCK, MOBTTZ: (1882^1936)* Austrian philosopher. 
Strongly influenced by Wittgenstein, he joined a discus- 
sion group in 1923 called the Vienna Circle, out of which 
grew logical positivism* He developed a form of psycho- 
logical hedonism in his book Problems of Ethics. Sdhlidc 
called the principles of logical positivism "standpointibss- 
ness/* 

SCHOPENHATJEH, ARTHOR: (1788-1860), Born in Danzig 
of a banker father and a novelist mother. He refused to 
enter his fathers work, but chose philosophy. He lectured 
widely but met with little success since other philosophers 
held the popular ear. This made hfai bitter, a bitterness 
which was sweetened slightly in later life as his fame grew. 
He wrote several books, among them: The World As Will 
and Idea and Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient 
Reason. 

SCOTXJS, JOHN DUNS: (i26s?~i3o8?), A member of the 
Franciscan order. After studying at Oxford he became a 
teacher there and later taught both at Paris and at Cologne. 

SHAFTESOTRY, LORD: (1671-1713). Moral philosopher 
and pupil of John Locke* He believed in the essential har- 
mony between egoism and altruism. In ethics, he was the 
first to apply the tern "moral sense* to man's instinctual 
drive to promote both the general welfare and individual 
happiness. His collected essays are found in Characteristics 
of Men* Manners, Opinions, Times. 

SMITH, ADAM: (1723-1790). Bom at Erkcaldy in Scot- 
land. He studied at Glasgow and at Oxford, but was not 
at all happy at Oxford. He thought the professors there 
were narrow-minded. This was because they refused to let 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 

him read Hume. His writings in political science have had 
wide influence. His most famous book is Wealth of Na- 
tions. 

SOCRATES: (469-399 B.C.)- Born in Athens, the son of 
a poor sculptor and a midwife. He lived a most erratic 
life and never wanted more than the simple necessities. 
He often went barefoot and dressed in rags to stress sim- 
plicity. He married but never had a satisfactory home life. 
Because his views were considered dangerous by the pow- 
erful political leaders of his time, he was condemned to 
death by the court of Athens and forced to drink a cup 
of hemlock. These final events are recorded in Plato's Dfc- 
logues, especially the Phaedo and Apology. 

SPENCER, HERBERT: (1820-1903). Utilitarian philoso- 
pher. He was for some time a civil engineer. In London he 
was intimate with a large circle of literary and philosophic 
geniuses and was greatly influenced in his work by them. 
His extensive writings include Essays on Education, The 
Man versus the State, and A System of Synthetic Phi- 
losophy. 

SPINOZA, BARXTCH: (1632-1677). He took the name 
Benedict. Born in Holland, the son of wealthy Portuguese- 
Jewish parents. Because of his views he was expelled from 
the synagogue and forced to wander about Europe. He 
gained a livelihood by grinding lenses. Among his major 
writings are Ethics and Treatise on the Improvement of 
Understanding. 

TKT.ESIO, BEBNABDINO: (1509-1588). Italian philoso- 
pher, born in Milan of noble family. With Bruno and Cam- 
panella, Telesio attacked the Aristotelian basis of scholas- 
ticism and stressed the importance of knowledge based on 
empirical scientific inquiry. At Naples he established his 
Academia Cosentma to further scientific methods of 
study, 



#94 BASIC TEACHINGS OF CHEAT PHILOSOPHERS 

THAJLES: (64O?~546? B.C.). Born in Miletus. Noted as a 
statesman, mathematician, and astronomer. He is said to 
have predicted the eclipse of May 28, 585. He is classified 
as one of the Seven Wise Men of Greece. 



PATELS (1886-1965). A Protestant theologian, 
Tfllich was boni in Germany. During World War I he 
served as field chaplain on the Western Front, and later 
taught theology and philosophy at Halle, Berlin, Breslau, 
Dresden, Leipzig, and Frankfort on the Main. After the 
rise of Hitler, Tiffitch came to the United States, becoming 
a citizen in 1940. He taught at Union Theological 
Seminary and at Harvard University. He is the author of 
The Courage to Be and other works. 



UNAMONO Y JXJGA, MictnEL DE: (1864-1936). A Span- 
ish creative writer and scholar, Unamuno was rector of the 
University of Salamanca. His outspoken criticism of the 
monarch, and of the dictator, Primo de Rivera, caused his 
removal from his post, and later his expulsion from Spain. 
He remained in eerile from 19524 to 1930; thereafter he re- 
sided in Spain again. His masterpiece is generally consid- 
ered to be The Tragic Sense of Life in Men and Peoples. 

VmcoBiNO X>A FELTBE: (1378-1446). Founder of the 
famous court school at Mantua which set the pattern for 
many such schools throughout Europe* 

VIVES, LtJixmoo: (1492-1540). Spanish scholar, born 
Juan Luis Vives at Valencia. After studying and teaching 
in France, Vives went to England and taught at Oxford. 
Later, having incurred the displeasure of Henry VIBE, he 
went to Bruges where he wrote most of his major works. 
Rejecting the authority of Aristotle and scholasticism, Vives 
published pioneer works on psychology and was one of the 
first to urge scientific induction as a philosophical and psy- 
chological method* One of his major works is De Aroma et 
Vita. 



BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES 

VOLTAIBJS: (1694-1778). His original name was Fran- 
9015 Marie Arouet. Born in Paris. He was imprisoned sev- 
eral times for his writings, which, include satirical roman- 
ces and plays as well as philosophical treatises. 

WHITEHEAJD, AUFRED NORTH: (1861-1947). British 
mathematician and philosopher, resident in the United 
States for many years, he criticized positivistic antireligious 
science. The obscurity of his style and his coinage of new 
technical terms makes much of his work difficult to under- 
stand. He received the Order of Merit in 1945. His writings 
include Science and the Modern World and Process and 
Reality. 

WTT.T.TAVT OF OCCAM: (1300? 1349). Known as *T>OO- 
tor Invincibilis** and "Venerabilis Inceptor.** An English 
scholastic philosopher and a member of the Franciscan 
order. He was first a pupil and then a rival of Duns Scotus. 
In his Dialogues, he laid the foundations for the modern 
theory of the independence of the secular government from 
the religious authorities. A vigorous and successful advocate 
of nominalism* 

WITTGENSTEIN; LUDWIG: (1889-1951). Born in Austria, 
Wittgenstein studied at Cambridge University, England, 
and returned there to teach in 1929. He became a natural- 
ized British subject in 1938. Although his major work 
Tractatus Logico-PhUosophicus led to the founding of the 
Vienna Circle, and his teaching in the 1930*5 and 1940*5 at 
Cambridge inspired the logical positivists, Wittgenstein felt 
that his ideas were often misunderstood and distorted by 
those who claimed to be his disciples. He did not hold with 
the positivists that statements not verifiable through sense- 
experience are useless or meaningless. Other published 
works are Philosophical Investigations and Remarks on the 
Foundations of Mathematics. 

XENOPHON: (43o?-355? B.C.). A Greek historian and 
disciple of Socrates, his Memorabitia of Socrates gives a 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GBEAT PHEUOSOPHEHS 

portrayal of that philosopher that differs markedly from the 
portrait given by Plato, 

ZENO OF ELEA: (4o?-43O? B.C.)- Greek philosopher 
of the Eleatic school According to Aristotle, Zeno was the 
first to employ the dialectical method. He is famous for 
**Zeno*s paradox^ the Idea that a moving object could 
never cover a given distance completely because, after hav- 
ing gone fa?lf fh^ way, it must cover half the remaining dis- 
tance, then half again, and so on, 



ZENO THE STOIC: (aaSP-a&j? B.C.)* Greek philosopher, 
founder of Stoicism* He integrated the views of Heraclitus* 
Plato, and Aristotle into a metaphysical and logical system 
which supported his ethical theories and program for living, 



INDEX 



Abelard, Peter, 22, 60, 89, 
137. 190, 215-16, 234-35, 



Alchemy, 28 
Alcuin, 215, 275 

Johannes, 194, 275 



Ambrose, St, 187, 275 
Anarchy, 180 
Anaragoras, 9, 229-30* 
Anasimander, 6-7, 102, 228, 

276 
Anaximines of Miletus, 7, 155, 

276 

Animism, 127 
Anselm, St, 22, ill, 190, 234* 

276 
Apologists, 19, 58, 88, 108-9* 

135, 160-61, 187, 213 
Aquinas, St Thomas, 23-24, 

6o~6i, 89-90, iiOr-13, 137, 

162, 190-91, 235, 252-53, 

276 
Aristotle, 12-15, 26, 57, 85- 

86, 105-6, 131-^32, 158-59, 

183-84, 211-12, 231-32, 
250, 276 

Astrology, 28 
Atihanasius, 110-11, 276 
Atomists, 10 ff., 16, 55, 156 
Augustine, St, 19-20, 59, 88- 
89, 109, 136, 161, 187, 233- 



34, 252, 276 



Bacon, Francis, 29-30, 63-64, 
114-15, 139-40, 163, 218, 



Bacon, Roger, 235-36, 277 
Basedow, Johann Bernhard, 

221, 277 

Bayle^ Pierre, 141, 277 
Behavioristic psydiokgy, 171 
Benedict, St, 214, 277 
Bentham, Jeremy, 97-98, 277 
Bergson, Henri, 51, *44> ^77 
Berkdey, George, 36-37, 66, 

117-18, 165-66, 240, 256, 

277-78 

Bernard of Chartres, 22 
Bodin, Jean, 194, 278 
Boehme, Jacob, 114, 278 
Bradley, F. H., 124, 244, 278 
Bruno, Giordano, 29, 114, 163, 

278 
Buber, Martin, 271, 278 



Callides, 83, 180 
Campanefla, Tommaso, 29, 

193, 278-79 

Camap, Rudolf, 268, 279 
Cameades, 107, 279 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT IHILOSOPHEBS 



Catechetical schools, 213 
Catedbmnens, 213 
Categorical imperative, 41, 95 
Change, problem of, ?& 
Chartres, School of, 22 
Cicero, Marcos TuEius, 213, 



City of God, The, 187-88 
C% of tfce Sun, The, 193 
dement of Alexandria, 213, 

379 
Comenins, John Amos, 218- 

19, 279 
Comte, Auguste, 74, 124, 171, 

201-2, 244, 260, 279-80 
Conceptualisin, 190 
Creative evolution, 51 
Croce, Benedetto, 269-70, 280 
Cumberland, Fichard, 93, 280 



Demiurge, 12, 104^5, 157 
Democritus, 10, 16, 82, 156, 

179,248,280 
Descartes, Rene, 31-32, 64, 92* 

113-16, 140^41, 163-64, 

238, 255, 280 
Dewey, John, 51, 77-78, 98, 



Epicurus, 16, 86, 132-33, 250, 

281 

Epiphenomenalism, 238 
Erigena, John Scotus, 21, 59- 

60, 109-10, 189, 215, 281 
Ethical problem, 81 
Ethics, 81 
Euthydemus, 83 
Evfl, 80 ff. 
Evolution, 48, 98 

264-66 



25, 244, 261-62, 280 
Dialectical process, 43-44, 123 
Dualism, 32 
Duns Scotus, John, 24^5, 113, 

137-38, I9it ^53, 



Eckhart, Meister, 26, 90, 113, 

280 

Education, 2078. 
Empedodes, 9, 5& 156* 247^ 

48,281 
Epicureans, 16, 17, 86, 106-7, 

132, 159, 184, 232 



Fate, 127, 129 ff. 

Fates, the, 128 

Fechner, Gustav Theodor, 46, 

123 
Fichte, J. G., 41-43, 69-70, 

9S-96, 121-22, 148, 168, 

222, 242-43, 258, 28l 

Freewill, 127&% 

Froebel, F. W. A*, 223-^4, 281 



Galileo, 28-^29, 236, 254, 

Gaunilo, 112 

God, the nature of, looff. 

Golden mean, 85 

Good, tie, 80 

Gof gicw, 180 

Great Society, 186 

Green, Thomas Hill, 151, 281- 

82 

Giotius, Hugo, 194, 282 
Guelincx, Arnold, 33, 141, 

^38-39 



Hamilton, Sir William, 124, 

282 

Hartley, David, 145, 282 
Hegel, G. W. F., 43-44, 71- 



INDEX 



299 



Hegel (confd) 

72, 122-23, 149-50* 199- 

300, 243, 258-59* s 8 * 
Hddegger, Martin, 265, 282 
Heraditus, 8, 54-55, 81-82, 

102-3, 129, 155-56, 228-29, 

247, 282-83 
Herbart, J. F., 44-45, 72-73, 

150, 169-70, 222-23, 243- 

44, ^59, 283 
Hesiod, 101-2 
Hobbes, Thomas, 30-31, 64, 

91-92, 115, 140, 163, 195- 

96, 218, 237-38, 283 
Holbach, Baton d", 145, 283 
Humanism, 62 
Hume, David, 37-38, 66-67, 

118-19, 143-44, 166, 240- 

41, 256-57, 283 
Hutcheson, Frauds, 94, 283- 

84 



Idea-ist, 12 
Idealism, 42, 44, 46 
Idealists, 49-50, 71, 74 
Ideas, 246 ff. 
Idols," 139, 232, 237 
Immortality, 153 ff 
Induction, method of, 30, 75 
Intuition, 51, 90 



James, William, 50, 77, 98, 
124-25, 151, 172, 244, 
284 

Jaspers, Karl, 265-66, 284 



Kant, 



4041, 68 



69, 94-95, 120-21, 146-48, 
167-68, 241-42* 257-58, 
284 



Kepler, Johannes, 236 
Kierkegaard, Stfren, 264-65, 
284 



Laissez-faire, 198, 204 

La Mettrie, Julien Offray de, 

14^284-85 

Lassalle, Ferdinand, 200 
Laws, 182 
Leibnitz, G. W., 39-40, 67, 

94, 119-20, 144-45, 166- 

67, 241, 257, 285 
Leudppus, 10, 156, 285 
Locke, John, 35-36, 65-66, 

93-93, H7, M2-43, 165, 

196-97, 219-20, 240, 256, 

285 

Logical positivism, 268-69 
Logos, 18, 108-9 
Lotze, Rudolf Hermann, 461, 

73-74, 123, 170, 285 
Luther, Martin, 217, 285 



Machiavelli, Niccolfc, 193-94, 

285 

Maistre, Joseph de, 200, 286 
Malebranche, Nicolas, 33, 164, 

^39, 286 

Maritafo, Jacques, 270-71, 286 
Marx, Karl, 200, 286 
Materialism, 31 
Matter, 226 ff. 

Mechanism, tiieory of, 31-8^ 
Memorabilia, 181 
Metaphysics, 133 
Mill, John Stuart, 47~48, 75- 

76, 97, 150-51, 202-3, 260, 

286 

Mfltoi, John, 217, 280-87 
Mind, 226 S. 
Medalists, no 



BASIC TEACHINGS OF GREAT PHILOSOPHERS 



Monads, 29, 39, 67, 144, 166, 

241 

Moore, George E., 268, 287 
Mysticism, 26, 112 



Newton, Sir Isaac, ng, 236, 287 
Nicholas of Cusa, 27, 114, 287 
Niebuhr, Reinhold, 270, 287 
Nietzsche, F. W., 74, 204-5, 

287 

Nominalism, 25, 6a 
Nominalists, 22, 25, 189, 251- 

52 
Noumenal world, 41 



Occaskmalists, 141, 239 
Organism, philosophy of, 267 
Origen, 213, 287-88 



Pantiheism, 21, 34, 43, 60 
Paracelsus, 28, 62, 236, 288 
Pannenides, 8-9, 229, 288 
Pascal, Blaise, 116, 141, 288 
Paulsen, Friedrich, 46, 288 
Pekghis, 136, 288 
Pestalozzi, J. H., 221-22, 288 
Philo, 18, 87-88, 107-8, 134, 

233,289 
Pkto, 10-12, 18, 26, 56-57, 

84-85, 104-5, I3i 157, 

181-83, 211, 230-31, 249* 

289 
PlotLaus, 18-19, 88, 108, 134- 

35. 289 

Positivism, 74, 171 
Pragmatism, 51, 171-72 
Pragmatists, 50, 79, 244 
Predestination, 59 
Priestley, Joseph, 145, 289 
Protagoras, 55, 83, 210, 248, 



289 
Psycho-physical parallelism, 

35, 240 

Pyrrho, 17, 232 
Pythagoras, 7, 129, 155, 289 
Pythagoreans, 7, 129, 155, 

178-79 



QuintilLan, 212-13, 290 



Ramus, Petrus, 62, 290 
Realism, 45 
Realists, 22, 189, 5i 
"Reals," 45, 72, 244 
Reid, Thomas, 38, 290 
Religious tradition, philosophy 

of, 270-71 

Republic, 182, 193, 211 
Richard of St. Victor, 112 
Roscelin, 22, 111, 190, 290 
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 68, 

146, 199, 220, 290 
Royce, Josiah, 49, 244, 290 
Russell, Bertrand, 78, 245, 

267-68, 290-91 



Saint-Simon, Claude Henri 

Rouvoy, Comte de, 201, 291 
Santayana, George, 52, 245, 

291 

Sartre, Jean-Paul, 266, 291 
Schelling, F. W. J., 43, 70, 

122, 148, 243, 291 
Schleiermacher, F. E. D., 71, 

122, 148-49* 169, 291-92 
Schlick, Moritz, 268, 29* 
Scholasticism, 23, 59, 215 
Schoolmen, 23, 189 
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 45-46, 

73, 96-97, 150, 170, 292 



Science, philosophy of, 266- 

68 

Seven liberal arts, 214-13 
Shaftesbury, Lord, 94* 292 
Skepticism, 38 

Skeptics, 17-18* 3107, 232-33 
Smith, Adam, 198, 292-93 
Socialism, 200 
Sociology, 2Q* 
Socrates, 56, 83-84, *<>4> 130- 

31, 181, 210-11, 249, 293 
Sophists, 55, 83, 104, 130, 

179-80, 209-10, 5248 
Soul the, 153& 
Spencer, Herbert, 48-49* 76, 

98, 124, 203-4, 260, 93 
Spinoza, Benedict, 33~35> 

65, 92, 116-17, 

42, 164, 196, 239-40, 

293 

Spirit, pMosopliy of, 269-70 
State, the, 175 
Stoics, 16-17, 58, 86-87, 107, 

133, 159, 185, 232, 251 
Sturm, Johann, 



INDEX 301 

Transmigration of souls, 158 
Trinity, the, no 



Telesio, Bernardino, 28, 62, 

162, 293 

Thales, 6 f 54, 103, 294 
Thinking, 246 ft 
Hirasymachiis, 83 
Tiffich, Paid, 270, 294 
Thnaeus, 12, 104, 157 
Toland, John, 145 



XTnamtmo y Juga, Miguel de, 



Universe, the, 5ff-, 53 & 
Unknowable, the, 48, 76, 124 
Unmoved mover, 15, 



Vittorino da Feltre, 216, 294 
Vives, Lndovico, 27, 62, 

63, 294 
Voltaire, 145, 198, 



Watson, John B^ 171 
Wedth of Nations, 198 
Whitehead, Alfred North, 

266-67, 295 

William of Champeanx, 60 
William of Occam, 25, 6a 

191-92, 295 
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 268, 

295 

Wilhehn, 46 



Xenophanes, 8, 103 
Xenophon, 181, 295-96 



Zeno of Elea, 9, 296 

Zeno the Stoic, 16, 133, 296 



ABOUT THE AUTHOR 

S. E. Frost, Jr. (1899-1978) taught in the Department of Educa- 
tion, Brooklyn College, City University of New York. He received 
a Ph.D. from Columbia University and a Bachelor of Divinity 
degree from Yale University. He spent many years in the study 
and teaching of the history and philosophy of education and is 
the author of a number of books on philosophy, religion, and 
education.